Skip to main content
Advertisement
Browse Subject Areas
?

Click through the PLOS taxonomy to find articles in your field.

For more information about PLOS Subject Areas, click here.

  • Loading metrics

How information about perpetrators’ nature and nurture influences assessments of their character, mental states, and deserved punishment

  • Julianna M. Lynch,

    Roles Conceptualization, Formal analysis, Investigation, Methodology, Writing – original draft

    Affiliation Department of Psychology, Franklin & Marshall College, Lancaster, Pennsylvania, United States of America

  • Jonathan D. Lane,

    Roles Conceptualization, Investigation, Methodology, Writing – review & editing

    Affiliation Department of Psychology and Human Development, Vanderbilt University, Nashville, Tennessee, United States of America

  • Colleen M. Berryessa,

    Roles Investigation, Methodology, Writing – review & editing

    Affiliation School of Criminal Justice, Center for Law and Justice, Rutgers University, Newark, New Jersey, United States of America

  • Joshua Rottman

    Roles Conceptualization, Formal analysis, Funding acquisition, Investigation, Methodology, Supervision, Writing – review & editing

    jrottman@fandm.edu

    Affiliation Department of Psychology, Franklin & Marshall College, Lancaster, Pennsylvania, United States of America

Abstract

Evidence of perpetrators’ biological or situational circumstances has been increasingly brought to bear in courtrooms. Yet, research findings are mixed as to whether this information influences folk evaluations of perpetrators’ dispositions, and subsequently, evaluations of their deserved punishments. Previous research has not clearly dissociated the effects of information about perpetrators’ genetic endowment versus their environmental circumstances. Additionally, most research has focused exclusively on violations involving extreme physical harm, often using mock capital sentences cases as examples. To address these gaps in the literature, we employed a “switched-at-birth” paradigm to investigate whether positive or negative information about perpetrators’ genetic or environmental backgrounds influence evaluations of a perpetrator’s mental states, character, and deserved punishment. Across three studies, we varied whether the transgression involved direct harm, an impure act that caused no harm, or a case of moral luck. The results indicate that negative genetic and environmental backgrounds influenced participants’ evaluations of perpetrators’ intentions, free will, and character, but did not influence participants’ punishment decisions. Overall, these results replicate and extend existing findings suggesting that perpetrators’ supposed extenuating circumstances may not mitigate the punishment that others assign to them.

Introduction

When individuals violate moral norms, others may consider multiple factors when deciding how much punishment the violators deserve. These judgments regarding persons’ culpability for violations are sometimes addressed in the legal system and also arise in more common, everyday folk evaluations. Studies in moral psychology are often designed to identify factors that influence blame and punishment judgments, including the harm caused by the action, the rules that are broken, violators’ intentionality, motivations, character, and psychological profiles [16]. This previous work reveals that people focus primarily on the severity of outcomes when deciding how much to punish a perpetrator [78]. However, demographic and dispositional qualities of the perpetrator (e.g., socioeconomic status; character traits) may mitigate the amount of punishment that third parties assign, both in legal contexts [912] and in everyday moral judgments [5].

As neuroscience advances and its applications become more widespread, research has begun to investigate how neuroscientific evidence influences people’s judgments of criminal behavior [1317]. This research is often described as evaluating the role of biological factors in folk evaluations of moral culpability. However, this interpretation is limited given that neurological, psychological, and behavioral phenomena are products of complex, dynamic interactions between genetic substrates and environmental factors, such as socio-economic status, parenting, and educational access [1820]. It is currently unclear whether the general public appreciates this complex interaction between genes and environment; for example, some people might inaccurately interpret neurological evidence as reflecting nature alone while others might assume that nurture plays a large role. In the current studies, we systematically tease apart biological and environmental factors in order to examine how individuals simultaneously weigh explicit information about violators’ nature and nurture when evaluating the violators’ mental states, character, and deserved punishment.

Previous research on the extent to which biological and environmental factors influence evaluations of transgressors has yielded mixed findings [2123]. In cases in which neuroscientific and psychological evidence humanizes the offender by providing a rationale for his or her behavior—for example, impaired reasoning ability—judgments of culpability and punishment typically decrease [3, 19, 2425]. For instance, mental disorders such as psychopathy, Autism Spectrum Disorder, and schizophrenia have been found to mitigate punishment because they provide insight into the mental state of the offender, and his or her impaired ability to reason, which reduces blame for wrongful actions [13, 19, 24]. Further, several studies have found that attributing behavior or characteristics to genetic influences can mitigate punishment assessments [2629].

On the other hand, evidence that highlights genetic substrates of disorders can also emphasize the stability of an antisocial trait, in turn increasing evaluations of violators’ dangerousness [13, 17, 25, 30] and inferences that violators are less likely to reform [3, 17, 21, 24]. Such evaluations of dangerousness, particularly related to genetics, can aggravate punishment assessments [5, 3133]. When a genetic predisposition for criminality is paired with negative environmental experiences, such as abuse, longer prison sentences are often recommended, particularly related to fear of the offenders’ dangerousness [34].

Here, to augment the existing literature, we contribute to the ongoing debate about how genetic and environmental factors influence assessments of perpetrators’ blameworthiness by directly separating information about perpetrators’ “nature” and their “nurture”. In one of the few prior studies to explore this issue, participants received separate genetic and environmental information about a defendant and participants were asked to make capital punishment decisions [3]. Our study differs from this previous research in several fundamental ways. First, Gordon and Greene [3] presented information about a perpetrator in a structure which mimicked a legal case, involving testimony from a forensic psychiatrist and an expert medical geneticist. Respondents were also pre-screened for their eligibility to participate in a real capital sentence case. Although these features increase the ecological validity of findings with regard to that specific circumstance (capital sentence decisions), it is not clear whether the findings would generalize to other populations, violations, and punishments. Our paradigm is more expansive, including a rich variety of more common wrongdoings: a simple harm violation, an impure act, and a case of moral luck. It is critical to study everyday transgressions, as previous literature hints that genetic explanations may be less relevant for punishment decisions in these situations as compared to criminal cases [34]. We measured the amount of punishment deserved on a continuum (as opposed to asking for dichotomous decisions, like those faced for capital sentence cases), which allowed us to capture greater variability in punishment ratings. Additionally, we isolated the specific genetic and environmental factors without including other dispositional, demographic, or mental health factors that could confound this information.

The current studies utilize a “switched-at-birth” task [3536] in order to clearly test how evidence about perpetrators’ innate factors and contextual factors influence third parties’ evaluations of blame and punishment. In this paradigm, participants are presented with a vignette in which a set of parents have a baby who accidentally gets switched at the hospital and is raised by a different set of parents. Participants are then asked whether the child will grow up to have characteristics like its birth parents or like the new parents. The current studies examine adults’ judgments, but we specifically created scenarios that could also eventually be used to examine developmental patterns in such judgments. Thus, scenarios in this study were worded such that they would be appropriate for children and for adults with a variety of educational backgrounds. To these ends, the switched-at-birth scenarios and questions employed relatively simple language and the perpetrator was described as being a child (this was specified as a seven-year-old child in Studies 2 and 3). Seven-year-olds are typically considered to have reached the “age of reason” in which they are judged as mature moral agents [37]. Thus, the vignettes seem appropriate for both adults and children, and the simplification of scientific terminology also provides accessibility for wider ranges of audiences who may not have a deep understanding of the nature of genetics or environmental factors. Overall, these aspects of the study design allowed us to precisely test for the effects of explicit information about nature, nurture, and their potential interaction, in a way more generalizable to folk accounts of blameworthiness and deserved punishment.

Although the actual origins of antisocial behavior appear to be influenced by gene-environment interactions that are still not fully understood [38], we aimed to examine people’s intuitions about person-centered factors that are of either nature- or nurture-based origin, as people often tend to think of these as separate and discrete causes [39]. Assessments of actions as either being caused by nature or nurture may influence the assumed degree of control a perpetrator is thought to have as over his or her actions, the goodness/dangerousness of the perpetrator, and the degree and type of punishment the perpetrator should receive for his/her actions. In our preregistration (https://osf.io/34v29/), we hypothesized that information about a perpetrator’s bad genes and information about their bad environment would independently mitigate judgments of their character (e.g., dangerousness), free will, blame, and deserved punishment. In light of previous evidence suggesting that extenuating circumstances do not heavily impact blame, another plausible hypothesis is that participants will focus primarily on the harmful consequences, rather than the protagonist’s nature or nurture when evaluating transgressors, and will not take genetic or environmental factors into account. As blame is often heavily contingent on negative outcomes [7], Studies 2 and 3 explored the extent to which information about a perpetrator’s genetic predispositions and environmental factors impact evaluations of the perpetrator in the absence of causing harmful outcomes—specifically, in cases of violating purity norms (Study 2) and in cases of moral luck (Study 3). All studies were approved by the Franklin & Marshall College Institutional Review Board, Protocol #R_2TTZdYDcDkHS4Nd. We have reported all measures, conditions, and data exclusions.

Study 1

Methods

Participants.

Participants were recruited through Amazon Mechanical Turk and paid $0.65 each. They were restricted to workers in the United States with a minimum HIT approval rate of 95%. The survey was completed by 201 participants, but 34 (17%) were excluded for providing one or more inaccurate answers on comprehension check questions (described below), leaving us with data from 167 participants (94 female, Mage = 37.65, SDage = 10.75). A power analysis using G*Power 3.1 [40] indicated that we required a minimum of 158 participants to detect medium-sized main effects (e.g., fs ≥ .25) with statistical power at the recommended .80 level and α = .05 [41]. With 167 participants, our actual power was .825.

Design and procedure.

Participants completed the survey on Qualtrics. After providing consent and identifying their gender, each participant was randomly assigned to read a single gender-matched scenario about an individual who was switched-at-birth (and thus raised by biologically unrelated parents) and who later committed a moral transgression. Specifically, vignettes described a story in which a baby (Jane or Fred) was born to parents who had either good, bad, or neutral genetic predispositions, but was accidentally switched at the time of birth and thus grew up with different parents in either a good, bad, or neutral environment. The first part of the story described the background of the birth parents (the “nature” component). Specifically, the story described the birth parents as having “something in their blood and brain that make them very [nice, mean, ordinary].” (We chose to use this language, rather than language about genes or DNA, in order to make the vignette broadly accessible to a range of audiences by describing proximate, familiar biological causes rather than distal, less familiar biological causes.) The second part of the story was the transition, which remained the same across all conditions and described Jane/Fred being switch-at-birth to biologically unrelated parents. Next, the living conditions of the unrelated parents were described (the “nurture” component). Lastly, participants received information that Jane/Fred had been caught throwing rocks at other children on the playground (the transgression). The transgression remained the same across all conditions. Thus, participants were randomly assigned to one of nine conditions resulting from a 3 (Genes: Good, Bad, or Neutral) X 3 (Environment: Good, Bad, or Neutral) design. Using the switched-at-birth design allowed us to juxtapose information about a perpetrator’s genetic versus environmental circumstances (see Fig 1 for details of the study design).

thumbnail
Fig 1. Flow chart of Study 1 switched-at-birth vignettes and condition assignment.

Scenarios with good, bad, or neutral genes were randomly paired with good, bad, or neutral environments for a total of nine possible conditions. All participants received the same transition and transgression.

https://doi.org/10.1371/journal.pone.0224093.g001

The impact of a perpetrator’s good, neutral, or bad genes and good, neutral, or bad rearing environment were explored for seven dependent variables, which participants responded to using 4-point Likert scales. First, participants were asked questions about the perpetrator’s intention to commit the transgression and the perpetrator’s decision-making ability. Questions 1 and 2 asked about the perpetrator’s mental states, specifically Intention: “Deep in her heart, did Jane/Fred want to hurt the other children?” and Free Will: “Could Jane/Fred have decided to be nice to the other boys and girls instead?” The choice options for Intention and Free Will were: Definitely not, Maybe not, Maybe yes, and Definitely yes. Next, Questions 3–5 asked about the Punishment that the perpetrator deserved: “How much trouble should Jane/Fred get in for hurting the other children?”; “Do you think Jane/Fred should be put in timeout?”; and “Do you think Jane/Fred should get their toys taken away?” The choice options for Time-Out and Toys Confiscated were: Definitely not, Maybe not, Maybe yes, and Definitely yes, and the choice options for Trouble were: None at all, A little bit, A lot, and Really a lot. Lastly, Questions 6 and 7 asked about the perpetrator’s Character traits: “How dangerous is Jane/Fred?” (choice options were: Not dangerous at all, A little dangerous, Pretty dangerous, and Very dangerous) and “How good is Jane/Fred?” (choice options were Not good at all, A little good, Pretty good, and Very good). These were followed by comprehension questions that asked: “What happened to Jane/Fred right after she was born?” (open-ended response); “What do you think about Mr. and Mrs. Smith? Are they really nice, sort of nice, sort of mean, or really mean?”; “What do you think about the place where Jane/Fred lives? Is it really good, sort of good, sort of bad, or really bad?” Incorrect answers on any of these three comprehension questions led to exclusion.

We attempted to form three composites from these seven variables: Mental States, Character, and Punishment, in line with a preregistered decision (https://bit.ly/2WHWb7X). However, questions about Intention and Free Will did not form a reliable composite involving Mental States (α = .292), so these questions were kept separate in analyses. (This was also true in Study 2, α = .299, and in Study 3, α = -.291). The questions assessing Dangerousness (reverse coded) and Goodness formed a reasonably reliable composite measure (α = .738), so these questions were combined (averaged) into a Character variable. Similarly, the Trouble, Timeout, and Toys Confiscated questions formed a reasonably reliable composite measure (α = .676), so these questions were combined (averaged) into a Punishment variable.

In this study and in Studies 2 and 3, participants were also asked to explain each of their ratings. These open-ended responses indicated that we successfully implied a deep, heritable biological characteristic in our vignettes. In Study 1, 15% of participants (14% in Study 2 and 9% in Study 3) spontaneously mentioned “genes”, “genetic”, “inherited”, or “DNA” when explaining their closed-ended evaluations. This frequency of unprompted references to genetic inheritance (approximately twice the frequency of references to “blood” or “brain”) suggests that participants generally interpreted information about the target’s blood and brain as being indicative of an underlying genetic predisposition, as was expected. Other details about these open-ended responses are beyond the scope of this paper, and are not discussed further.

Finally, because previous work has indicated that essentialist beliefs could influence the perceived relevance of a person’s genetic background for evaluating their blameworthiness [3, 13, 17, 19, 24, 31, 42], we administered questionnaires to assess individual differences in overall essentialist tendencies at the end of this study and the two subsequent studies. In Study 1, we combined validated scales measuring overall genetic essentialism [43] and social essentialism [44]. Study 2 incorporated a measure of overall genetic essentialism [43], and Study 3 included additional measures of discreteness (i.e., distinctness or uniqueness), informativeness (i.e., revealing or instructive indications of personal dispositions), and biological basis [45]. In all studies, these measures were presented after participants had answered all questions about the focal scenarios. These measures did not achieve internal consistency in the first study, and did not yield informative findings in Studies 2 or 3, so we do not discuss them further (see the S1 File for the scales that were used; results are available from the authors upon request).

Results

Four two-way Analyses of Variance (ANOVAs) were conducted to evaluate the effects of information about the perpetrator’s Genes (3: Good, Bad, or Neutral) and the perpetrator’s Environment (3: Good, Bad, or Neutral) on participants’ evaluations of the perpetrator’s intention, free will, character, and deserved punishment (see Fig 2). These analyses revealed a main effect of Genes on evaluations of Free Will, F(2, 158) = 6.852, p = .001, η2p = .080, which were lower when the perpetrator possessed bad genes as opposed to neutral genes, p = .008, or good genes, p = .002 (these and all subsequent post-hoc tests are corrected using Tukey’s HSD). There was also a main effect of Genes on evaluations of the perpetrator’s Intention, F(2, 158) = 3.404, p = .036, η2p = .041, which were elevated when the perpetrator possessed bad genes versus good genes, p = .038. Finally, there was a main effect of Genes on evaluations of Character, F(2, 158) = 5.029, p = .008, η2p = .060, which were more positive when perpetrators possessed good genes as opposed to bad genes, p = .010, and marginally more positive when they had good genes as opposed to neutral genes, p = .065. There was no effect of Genes on Punishment ratings, F(2, 158) = .524, p = .593, η2p = .007. Overall, information about the quality of perpetrators’ genes influenced evaluations of their free will, intention, and character, but did not influence evaluations of how much punishment they deserved for their transgression.

thumbnail
Fig 2. Study 1 results.

Participants’ average ratings (ranging from 1 to 4) of how much the perpetrator (a) desired to commit the transgression; (b) could have instead decided to act nicely; (c) had a positive character; (d) deserved punishment. Error bars represent standard errors of the mean.

https://doi.org/10.1371/journal.pone.0224093.g002

These ANOVAs also uncovered an effect of Environment on evaluations of Character, F(2, 158) = 4.909, p = .009, η2p = .059, driven by participants’ evaluations of the perpetrator as having a more positive disposition if they had been raised in a neutral versus bad environment, p = .005. There were no main effects of Environment on any other dependent variable; Intention: F(2, 158) = .049, p = .952, η2p = .001; Free Will: F(2, 158) = .985, p = .376, η2p = .012; Punishment: F(2, 158) = 1.117, p = .330, η2p = .014.

The sole interaction of information about the perpetrator’s Genes and Environment was found for evaluations of their Free Will, F(4, 158) = 2.496, p = .045, η2p = .059. Thus, the main effect of information about genes on evaluations of free will (reported earlier) was moderated by information about the perpetrator’s environment. When the perpetrator was raised in a bad environment, information about their genes was irrelevant. However, when the perpetrator was raised in a neutral or positive environment, they were judged to have greater free will if they had neutral genes (neutral environment: p = .051; good environment: p = .002) or good genes (neutral environment: p = .001; good environment: p = .003) as opposed to bad genes. There was no significant interaction between Genes and Environment for any other dependent measure; Intention: F(4, 158) = .578, p = .679, η2p = .014; Character: F(4, 158) = .814, p = .518, η2p = .020; Punishment: F(4, 158) = .992, p = .414, η2p = .024. Thus, while the quality of perpetrators’ upbringing (i.e., environment) only directly influenced participants’ evaluations of their character, it interacted with information about the perpetrator’s genes to affect inferences about their free will. But this information about the perpetrator’s upbringing showed no influence on inferences about the perpetrator’s desire to hurt others or judgments of how much punishment they deserve.

Discussion

Our results reveal that individuals account for the quality of a perpetrator’s genetic background when inferring the perpetrator’s intention to commit a transgression and their free will to commit a transgression (particularly in decent rearing environments), indicating that “bad genes” increase attributions of desire to commit immoral actions while reducing assumed controllability over these actions. This is consistent with previous research indicating that genetic information may affect inferences about persons’ mental states, ability to reason, and personal jurisdiction over their actions [3, 13, 17, 19, 2425]. Genetic background, in addition to the quality of a perpetrator’s environment, was also taken into consideration when evaluating the perpetrator’s character. The more negative the perpetrator’s genetic background (i.e., the meaner the birth parents) and the more negative the environment in which the perpetrator was raised, the more negatively participants evaluated the perpetrator’s character. This is consistent with previous findings that genetic evidence conveying abnormal or negative information about an individual can sometimes increase impressions of dangerousness because the behavior is considered more persistent and enduring in nature [3, 17, 21, 24].

Yet, neither the quality of the perpetrator’s genes nor the quality of their environment influenced the amount of punishment that individuals assigned to the perpetrator. Thus, qualities of the perpetrator’s background influenced individuals’ impression of the perpetrator’s mental states and character, but had no bearing on their punishment decisions. This finding suggests that the crime itself (i.e., causing harm) may be more influential than the perpetrator’s background when assigning punishment. Because the transgression (screaming and throwing rocks) was an egregious case of harm, participants may have focused wholly on the outcome of the action rather on the perpetrator’s background when making punishment decisions. If so, then the influence of background information might be more apparent in cases of harmless transgressions, for example, for violations of moral purity. Thus, in Study 2, we compared the effects of background information for two types of violations: a harm violation and a purity violation.

Study 2

Punishment appears to function as a result of a two-part system of blaming: (1) a person violates a moral code or social norm and (2) correspondingly is cognitively and socially blamed for the violation [4]. Society recognizes the wrongness of the violation and attempts to alter or reform the behavior by implementing punishing consequences, either socially or legally. Additionally, information about the person and events that precede the violation often influence judgments of wrongness and blameworthiness. For example, a person’s intentions and the amount of harm caused by their actions are taken into account when determining how much blame and punishment they deserve [4, 7].

However, evaluations of purity transgressions have been found to operate differently from harm transgressions [4648]. When considering strange or taboo behaviors (e.g., incest, cannibalism), people are more likely to provide person-centered explanations for why the actor committed the violation, meaning that they consider the perpetrator’s character traits rather than the qualities of their action or its outcome [49]. Because judgments of purity violations involve a greater focus on the character of transgressors, it is possible that judgments of people who violate purity norms may rely more heavily on information about the perpetrators’ genetic and environmental histories, relative to judgments of people who violate harm norms. In other words, even though the results from Study 1 indicated that genetic and environmental backgrounds are irrelevant for folk punishment decisions, this may differ for transgressions that do not have salient consequences or victims.

Similar to the previous study, Study 2 was an investigation of how genes and rearing environments influence evaluations of intention, free will, character, and punishment. However, in Study 2, we compared the harmful violation from Study 1 (throwing rocks) with a purity violation (public nudity/offensive language) to investigate if the type of transgression mattered when determining the influences of nature and nurture on punishment and other judgments. Because no direct harm was caused in the purity violation, and previous research has shown that character is a more relevant factor for evaluating impure acts compared to harmful acts [4950], we expected information about the perpetrator’s genetic and environmental background to play a larger role in participants’ punishment decisions.

Methods

Participants.

Participants were recruited through Amazon Mechanical Turk and paid $0.60 each. They were again restricted to workers in the United States with a minimum HIT approval rate of 95%. The survey was completed by 154 participants, but 14 (9%) were excluded for providing one or more inaccurate answers on comprehension check questions, leaving us with data from 140 participants (79 female, Mage = 34.09, SDage = 10.12). A power analysis using G*Power [40] indicated that we required at least 128 participants to detect medium-sized main effects (e.g., fs ≥ .25), with statistical power = .80 and α = .05. With 140 participants, our actual power was .836.

Design and procedure.

Participants completed the survey on Qualtrics. After providing consent and identifying their gender, each participant was randomly assigned to read a single gender-matched scenario in one of eight conditions, which varied by type of Genes (Good or Bad), type of Environment (Good or Bad), and type of Transgression (Harm, which involved throwing rocks and yelling, or Purity, which involved running around naked and shouting obscenities). Just as in Study 1, the switched-at-birth paradigm [3536] was used, and this information was followed by a description of a single moral transgression. Unlike Study 1, no neutral conditions of genes or environments were included.

The harm transgression remained the same as in Study 1, with the exception of specifying the age of the perpetrator, saying that he/she is seven years old at the time of the transgression. The new purity violation was: “Jane is now seven years old. One day during recess, Jane decides to take off all her clothes and she starts running around the playground naked. She shouts dirty words while she runs” (see Fig 3). The participants were then asked seven different questions, each testing a different dependent variable (Intention, Free Will, Goodness, Dangerousness, Punishment, Timeout, Toys Confiscated). The variables examined were the same as in Study 1, but the phrasing of the Questions 1–3 were changed slightly in the Purity condition to reflect the new transgression. Question 1 was: “Deep in her heart, did Jane/Fred want to run around the playground like this?”. Question 2 was: “Could Jane/Fred have decided to keep her clothes on and play nicely with the others instead?”. Question 3 was: “How much trouble should Jane/Fred get in for running around the playground like this?”

thumbnail
Fig 3. Flow chart of Study 2 switched-at-birth vignettes and condition assignment.

Scenarios with good or bad genes were randomly paired with either good or bad environments and then randomly assigned to either the harm or purity violation, resulting in a total of eight possible conditions. Every participant received the same transition.

https://doi.org/10.1371/journal.pone.0224093.g003

All questions were recorded on the same 4-point Likert scales used in Study 1 and comprehension check questions were also included. One question was changed to provide more clarification: “Remember, Mrs. Smith is the person who got pregnant with Jane. What do you think about Mrs. Smith?” Responses were recorded using the same scale as in Study 1. As in Study 1, we created a Character composite which included questions about Dangerousness (reverse coded) and Goodness (α = .595); and a Punishment composite which included the Trouble, Timeout, and Toys Confiscated questions (α = .703). Although the reliability of the Character composite is modest, we retain it here given that the same composite is used (and has an α > .70) in Studies 1 and 3.

Results

A series of four three-way ANOVAs tested for effects of Genes (Good vs. Bad), Environment (Good vs. Bad), and Transgression (Harm vs. Purity) on evaluations of intention, free will, character, and deserved punishment (see Fig 4). These analyses revealed a marginal effect of Genes on evaluations of the perpetrator’s Character, F(1, 132) = 3.513, p = .063, η2p = .026, as evaluations of character were more positive when the perpetrator possessed good (vs. bad) genes. All other effects of Genes were non-significant; Intention: F(1, 132) = .232, p = .631, η2p = .002; Free Will: F(1, 132) = 1.715, p = .193, η2p = .013; Punishment: F(1, 132) = .147, p = .702, η2p = .001. Thus, the perpetrator’s possession of good or bad genes slightly influenced evaluations of character, but did not influence any other morally relevant assessments.

thumbnail
Fig 4. Study 2 results.

Participants’ average ratings (ranging from 1 to 4) of how much the perpetrator (a) desired to commit the transgression; (b) could have instead decided to act nicely; (c) had a positive character; (d) deserved punishment. Error bars represent standard errors of the mean.

https://doi.org/10.1371/journal.pone.0224093.g004

There were main effects of Environment on evaluations of Intention, F(1, 132) = 3.939, p = .049, η2p = .029; Free Will, F(1, 132) = 4.970, p = .027, η2p = .036; and Character, F(1, 132) = 7.326, p = .008, η2p = .053. When a perpetrator was raised in a good (compared to bad) environment, participants inferred that they had greater free will and intent to commit the transgression, and evaluated them as having a more positive character. Environment did not significantly affect the Punishment decisions: F(1, 132) = .513, p = .475, η2p = .004.

There was a main effect of the type of Transgression (Harm vs. Purity) on evaluations of Character, F(1, 132) = 19.599, p < .001, η2p = .129, and Punishment, F(1, 132) = 22.338, p < .001, η2p = .145. For the harmful transgression, character evaluations were more negative and punishment decisions were harsher. The other main effects of Transgression were not significant; Intention: F(1, 132) = .349, p = .556, η2p = .003; Free Will: F(1, 132) = .021, p = .885, η2p = .000. Overall, the type of transgression committed influenced evaluations of character and deserved punishment, but did not influence evaluations of mental states.

There were no significant two-way or three-way interactions for any dependent variables, with all ps > .07. Thus, significant effects (and null effects) of Genes and Environment on evaluations of the perpetrator were similar for all dependent variables, whether the perpetrator had committed a moral violation or purity violation (see S1 File).

Discussion

Similar to results from Study 1, in Study 2 we found that the quality of a perpetrator’s genes and environment influenced judgments of their dispositional tendencies. When the perpetrator possessed bad (vs. good) genes, they were judged to have poorer character. When the perpetrator was raised in a bad (vs. good) environment, participants surmised that they had less free will. Whereas in Study 1 perpetrators with bad genes were judged to have greater intent, here, perpetrators who grew up in a positive environment were judged to have greater intent. Similar to Study 1, perpetrators who were raised in a positive environment were also judged to have greater free will in committing the transgression, as well as a greater desire to do so.

Yet, as in Study 1, the quality of the perpetrator’s genes and environment had no influence on judgments of how much punishment they should receive. Punishment decisions were influenced only by the type of transgression (harm vs. purity violation); the perpetrator received greater punishment after committing the harm violation than after committing the purity violation. The type of transgression also influenced character judgments, such that the perpetrator who committed a harm violation was evaluated more negatively. The significant effect of transgression type may be limited to the specific transgressions that we chose. To test the robustness of this effect, future research can use a broader range of transgressions, and ensure that harm and purity transgressions are matched on severity.

In Study 2, we found that the type of transgression influences punishment assessments, much more so than information about the perpetrator’s background. This was true even for a transgression of moral purity that involved no physical harm and no specific victim. In Study 3, we attempt to divert participants’ focus from the transgression even further, by turning to a case in which the perpetrator has no causal role in a negative outcome, by virtue of being lucky.

Study 3

The wrongness of an action does not completely determine how that action will be punished. Individuals also take into account actors’ intentions and the amount of harm caused by their actions [7]. In general, when there are no negative consequences of an action, there is no reason to punish the actor, as conveyed by the adage, “no harm, no foul”. However, the phenomenon of “moral luck”–in which some negligent actors can happen to avoid harm by sheer chance, while others who act in similar ways can end up being much less fortunate—indicate that people’s intuitions in these cases are not so clear-cut. When it is apparent that the punishment meted out for a harmful outcome is at least partially dependent on luck, it becomes prudent to begin assessing the relevant mental, dispositional, and situational characteristics that increased the likelihood of the outcome [5152]. In line with this reasoning, we hypothesized that a norm violation which causes no direct harm could potentially lead to an increased focus on the genetic and environmental factors that led the perpetrator to become a particular “kind” of person, and thus influence punishment decisions. Specifically, we predicted that if two actors engaged in the same negligent action (reckless rock-throwing), resulting in a victim being injured, the morally lucky agent who threw rocks but did not directly cause the harm would receive some small amount of punishment that would depend in part on the actor’s genetic and environmental background.

Similar to Studies 1 and 2, Study 3 investigated how information about genes and environments influence evaluations of intention, free will, character, and punishment. We included all of these dependent variables to keep our sequence of questioning similar to that of Studies 1 and 2 (so that we could neatly compare findings across studies), but our primary focus in this study was on participants’ punishment decisions. In Study 3, we compared an accidentally harmful violation with a morally lucky situation that caused no direct harm. These scenarios were designed to investigate whether individuals’ punishment decisions are influenced by an actor’s genetic and environmental background in a case where there is the potential to cause harm, but no actual harm is caused (because of moral luck). In this study, the scenarios described the main character and his/her friend both throwing rocks off a bridge, such that they were equally negligent. In the Direct Harm condition, the main actor threw a rock which hit a person below. In the No Direct Harm scenario, the actor’s friend threw the rock which hit the person below. Although both the main actor and the friend engaged in the same actions and had the same intentions, the cause of the outcome in each scenario differed. We were particularly interested in whether background information regarding genes and environment influenced how people made punishment decisions about the actor who was morally lucky.

Methods

Participants.

Participants were recruited through Amazon Mechanical Turk and paid $0.80 each. They were again restricted to workers in the United States with a minimum HIT approval rate of 95%. The survey was completed by 198 participants, but 50 (25%) were excluded for providing one or more inaccurate answers on comprehension check questions, leaving data from 148 participants (89 female, 1 non-binary, Mage = 36.90, SDage = 11.90). A power analysis using G*Power [40] indicated that we required at least 128 participants to detect medium-sized main effects (e.g., fs ≥ .25), with statistical power = .80 and α = .05. Having 148 participants, our actual statistical power was .856.

Design and procedure.

Participants completed the survey on Qualtrics. After providing consent and identifying their gender, each participant was randomly assigned to read a single gender-matched scenario in one of eight conditions, which varied by type of genes (Good or Bad), type of environment (Good or Bad), and type of outcome (Direct Harm or No Direct Harm). (The participant who did not report a binary gender received the scenario with a male character.) As in Studies 1 and 2, the switched-at-birth paradigm was used, with the possibility for being presented with information about a positive or negative genetic predisposition and a positive or negative rearing environment. In the Direct Harm condition, the vignette ended with a transgression involving throwing rocks from the top of a hill with a friend and accidentally hitting a person below, causing a severe injury. In the No Direct Harm condition, the main character was also throwing rocks, but his/her friend directly caused the severe injury to the person below (see Fig 5).

thumbnail
Fig 5. Flow chart of Study 3 switched-at-birth vignettes and condition assignment.

Scenarios with good or bad genes were randomly paired with either good or bad environments and then randomly assigned to either the Direct Harm or No Direct Harm condition, resulting in a total of eight possible combinations. All participants received the same transition.

https://doi.org/10.1371/journal.pone.0224093.g005

The participants were then asked seven questions, examining the same variables as in Studies 1 and 2; however some phrasing was changed to reflect the new transgression. Question 1 was: “Deep in her heart, did Jane/Fred want the rock to hit that person?” Question 2 was: “Could Jane/Fred have decided not to throw rocks and play nicely on the playground instead?” Question 3 was: “How much trouble should Jane/Fred get in for throwing rocks?” Questions 4–7 (punishment assessments, dangerousness, and goodness) remained the same as Studies 1 and 2. In the No Direct Harm condition, even though it was the friend of Jane or Fred who threw the rock that injured a person, participants were still asked about Jane’s or Fred’s role in the transgression (given that s/he was being equally negligent). All questions were recorded on the same 4-point Likert scales used in the previous two studies. Comprehension check questions remained the same as in Study 2, but also included one additional question to ensure that participants understood the details of the transgression: “Who hit the person with the rock?” As in the first two studies, we created a Character composite which included questions about the actor’s Dangerousness (reverse coded) and Goodness (α = .704); and a Punishment composite which included the Trouble, Timeout, and Toys Confiscated questions (α = .755).

Results

Utilizing a series of four 3-way ANOVAs, we tested for effects of information about the actor’s Genes (Good vs. Bad), Environment (Good vs. Bad), and Outcome (Direct Harm vs. No Direct Harm) on evaluations of intention, free will, character, and deserved punishment (see Fig 6). We found a significant main effect of Genes for evaluations of Intention, F(1, 140) = 12.799, p < .001, η2p = .084; Free Will, F(1, 140) = 4.594, p = .034, η2p = .032; and Character, F(1, 140) = 5.839, p = .017, η2p = .040. Participants who read about the actor’s bad genes reported that they more strongly desired to commit the transgression, had less free will, and had worse character. There was no effect of Genes on ratings of Punishment, F(1, 140) = 1.630, p = .204, η2p = .012.

thumbnail
Fig 6. Study 3 results.

Participants’ average ratings (ranging from 1 to 4) of how much the perpetrator (a) desired to commit the transgression; (b) could have instead decided to act nicely; (c) had a positive character; (d) deserved punishment. Error bars represent standard errors of the mean.

https://doi.org/10.1371/journal.pone.0224093.g006

There was a significant main effect of Environment on evaluations of Character, F(1, 140) = 19.373, p < .001, η2p = .122; participants evaluated the actor more positively when they had a good (vs. bad) environmental background. There were no other significant main effects of Environment; Intention: F(1, 140) = 1.324, p = .252, η2p = .009; Free Will: F(1, 140) = .825, p = .365, η2p = .006; Punishment: F(1, 140) = .173, p = .678, η2p = .001.

The only variable that influenced Punishment decisions was the type of Outcome (Direct Harm vs. No Direct Harm), F(1, 140) = 7.657, p = .006, η2p = .052. The amount of punishment assigned to the actor was greater when they accidentally caused harm than when the actor performed the same actions but did not directly cause harm (i.e., was morally lucky). There were no other significant effects of transgression type; Intention: F(1, 140) = .260, p = .611, η2p = .002; Free Will: F(1, 140) = .125, p = .725, η2p = .001; Character: F(1, 140) = 1.732, p = .190, η2p = .012. Thus, the type of transgression influenced punishment assessments, but not the other morally relevant assessments, such as the actor’s character, intent, or level of control for committing the transgression.

There were no significant two-way or three-way interactions for any dependent variables (all ps > .08), suggesting that the effects of Genes, Environment, and Outcome did not moderate one another (see S1 File).

Discussion

Similar to Studies 1 and 2, the actor’s genetic and environmental background influenced evaluations of their mental states and their character. When the actor possessed bad (vs. good) genes, participants inferred that the actor more strongly desired to commit the transgression, had less free will, and had poorer character. When the actor was raised in a bad (vs. good) environment, participants also inferred that they had a more negative character. Yet, the effects of information about the actor’s genes and environment did not translate into effects on punishment assessments, replicating and extending our findings from Studies 1 and 2.

The only factor that did influence punishment assessments in Study 3 was the outcome of the transgression: despite the two actors behaving identically, greater punishment was delivered when the actor’s behavior led to harm. This finding is similar to that of Study 2, in that the nature of the transgression influenced punishment assessments, whereas information about actor’s genes or environment did not. This is consistent with previous research highlighting that the outcomes of violations tend to motivate punishment, even whether the actor does not intend for the outcome to occur [7, 53].

Unlike in Study 2, the type of transgression in Study 3 (throwing rocks and accidentally hitting a person, or throwing rocks and being morally lucky) did not affect evaluations of the actor’s character. This suggests that participants interpreted the action (throwing rocks), rather than the particular outcome of the actions, as a better reflection of the actor’s character. It is possible that participants largely considered accidentally hurting someone and being lucky as uncontrollable factors, rather than outcomes related to the actor’s dispositional tendencies.

General discussion

Decades of psychological and biological research have revealed how people’s background circumstances—both genetic and environmental—influence how they think, act, and the kind of people they become. Our studies highlight that associations between individuals’ background circumstances and their psychological and behavioral outcomes are embedded in folk psychology; participants modulated their evaluations of a perpetrator’s mental states and dispositions in accordance with information about the perpetrator’s birth family and rearing environment. In Studies 1 and 3, the perpetrator’s genetic background tended to be a particularly salient factor in participants’ inferences about their intentions and free will, whereas in Study 2 the perpetrator’s rearing environment tended to be a salient factor in participants’ inferences about their free will. In all three studies, character assessments were especially malleable, influenced by information about both genetic and environmental backgrounds. Thus, while we cannot confidently conclude that perceptions of mental states are reliably influenced by information about nature or nurture, there is ample evidence to suggest that people rely on information about biological and environmental circumstances to make assessments of perpetrators’ character traits.

Strikingly, despite the impact of genetic and environmental information on participants’ inferences about internal characteristics of perpetrators, these factors were irrelevant in participants’ evaluations of the amount of punishment that perpetrators deserved. Previous research has found that moral evaluations are directly influenced by information about actors’ mental states [7, 53] and character [5455]. Thus, there was reason to predict that background characteristics would affect punishment decisions, by virtue of the perpetrator’s background influencing judgments of their intention, free will, and character. However, even though information about background characteristics reliably influenced participants’ evaluations of the perpetrator’s mental states and character across all three studies, this never translated into differences in punishment judgments. Instead, evaluations about the deservingness of punishment were based only on the nature of the crime; they were robustly immune to various extenuating circumstances.

One explanation for the null effect of background factors on punishment assessments is that punishment decisions (particularly as compared to assessments of moral wrongness) rely heavily on the outcomes of actors’ behaviors [7]. Empirical and theoretical work has indicated that the signaling and pedagogical functions of punishment are most effective when punishment decisions are primarily driven by the presence of direct consequences, rather than by invisible factors such as a person’s internal dispositions [8]. Previous research on extenuating circumstances has almost exclusively involved harmful actions [9, 24], and so it was reasonable to surmise that those outcomes were so egregiously negative that they might have overshadowed the relevance of background circumstances. However, we reduced the salience of outcomes in Studies 2 and 3, which involved an impure action or a negligent but inconsequential action, respectively, and punishment decisions remained unaffected by the actors’ genetic and environmental histories. The current studies thus provide strong evidence that, across a variety of circumstances, background factors seem to be largely irrelevant in laypersons’ punishment decisions, even in the absence of direct harm. This converges with findings from previous studies [56], in which the genetic backgrounds of perpetrators who commit everyday transgressions (e.g., stealing a cookie), have no influence on participants punishment judgments. Additionally, previous work has found that, although genetic information mitigated evaluations of the perpetrator’s control and increased beliefs about their reoffending, genetic information did not affect sentencing decisions [57].

However, the type of outcome in the current studies (i.e., a harm vs. a purity violation, or a directly harmful vs. morally lucky outcome) did influence the harshness of participants’ punitive evaluations; thus, it is neither the case that participants ignored details of the transgressions nor that their punishment decisions were uniform and unmalleable. Similarly, information about genetic and environmental backgrounds influenced evaluations of mental states and character, and thus it is not the case that participants ignored the details of the actors’ histories. Rather, these null effects are evidence against the relevance of information about perpetrators’ genetic or environmental backgrounds in laypersons’ punishment decisions.

Future research will need to further confirm these null effects—for instance, by testing whether they are due to nullifying competing effects across participants (with some participants treating genetic factors as mitigating and some participants treating genetic factors as aggravating) [24]. Although we did not find compelling evidence of genetic information acting as a “double edged sword”, it will be important for future work to help reconcile our findings with some of the positive effects that have been previously uncovered by other researchers (e.g., [2629]). For instance, future research could investigate whether participants’ political ideologies moderate the effect of information about genetic or environmental factors on punishment decisions. If liberals and conservatives react to information about biological and environmental circumstances in opposing ways, these tendencies could negate each other when averaging across a full sample. In addition, future research could examine the extent to which individual differences in empathy or sympathy toward a perpetrator moderates the impact of information about that perpetrator’s background.

Unlike most previous studies that have investigated severe transgressions such as murder and harsh sentences such as capital punishment [3, 19, 21], the current research focused on more everyday moral transgressions (e.g., throwing rocks on a playground) and more typical sanctions (e.g., time-out). Because judgments of transgressions are heavily influenced by the depravity or severity of the action, as well as their effects on victims (e.g., [58]), these judgments may also be differentially affected by a perpetrator’s background characteristics. Thus, future research could use the current “switched-at-birth” paradigm to examine how adult participants may make judgments of punishment about transgressions of a range of severity, in order to see if the null effects observed in this research hold across such transgressions with a broad range of perceived depravity and negative consequences.

The vignettes used in the current studies were designed to be accessible to participants with varying educational backgrounds; for example, we did not include medical, biological, or sociological jargon to describe the perpetrators’ biological and environmental circumstances. These same vignettes may be used with child participants, to examine how the inferences and judgments uncovered here tend to unfold across childhood. Although the language used in the vignettes was chosen to make the stimuli accessible to participants across a wide range of educational backgrounds, the generality of some language (e.g., referring to something in the perpetrators’ “blood and brain” rather than specific genetic variants) could be a limitation. Extensions of the current work could include more precise language about perpetrators’ genetic and environmental backgrounds. Additional work may also investigate whether the sequencing of information (e.g., whether extenuating circumstances are described before or after transgressions) alters punishment decisions, or whether perpetrators’ backgrounds may matter more for punishment decisions regarding premeditated vs. spontaneous transgressions. Laying a foundation for this future work, the current studies identify a robust dissociation between information about perpetrators’ histories and laypersons’ punishment decisions. This contradicts assumptions embedded within the U.S. legal system; for example, background character evidence is admissible during sentencing phases in certain cases, yet the current studies (and prior work) suggest that such evidence may actually have little bearing on sentences [59]. It is incumbent on researchers to identify ways in which such evidence can be presented such that it meaningfully shapes punishment decisions.

Supporting information

Acknowledgments

We are grateful to Emily Conder, Christopher Jaeger, Xinjie Zhao, and Valerie Zizik for their assistance in the initial conceptualization of the research and to Lulu Gomez, Nicole Kolmstetter, and Jennifer Shabrach for their assistance with coding open-ended responses.

References

  1. 1. Alicke MD. Culpable causation. J Pers Soc Psychol. 1992;63(3):368–378.
  2. 2. Bartels DM. Principled moral sentiment and the flexibility of moral judgment and decision making. Cognition. 2008 Sep;108(2):381–417. pmid:18486121
  3. 3. Gordon N, Greene E. Nature, nurture, and capital punishment: How evidence of a genetic environment interaction, future dangerousness, and deliberation affect sentencing decisions. Behav Sci Law. 2018 Jan-Feb;36(1):65–83. pmid:28881042
  4. 4. Malle BF, Guglielmo S, Monroe AE. A theory of blame. Psychol Inq. 2014 May 20;25(2):147–186.
  5. 5. Uhlmann EL, Pizarro DA, Diermeier D. A person-centered approach to moral judgment. Perspect Psychol Sci. 2015 Jan 10;10(1):72–81. pmid:25910382
  6. 6. Young L, Tsoi L. When mental states matter, when they don’t, and what that means for morality. Soc Personal Psychol Compass. 2013 Aug 13;7(8):585–604.
  7. 7. Cushman F. Crime and punishment: Distinguishing the roles of causal and intentional analyses in moral judgment. Cognition. 2008 Aug;108:353–380. pmid:18439575
  8. 8. Cushman F. Punishment in humans: From intuitions to institutions. Philos Compass. 2015 Jan 28;10(2):117–133.
  9. 9. Berryessa CM. The effects of psychiatric and “biological” labels on lay sentencing and punishment decisions. J Exp Criminol. 2018. Jun;14(2):241–256.
  10. 10. Franklin TW. Sentencing outcomes in US district courts: Can offenders’ educational attainment guard against prevalent criminal stereotypes? Crime Delinq. 2017 Feb;63(2):137–165.
  11. 11. Jordan K L, Freiburger TL. The effect of race/ethnicity on sentencing: Examining sentence type jail length, and prison length. J Ethn Crim Justice. 2015 Jan 20;13(3):179–196.
  12. 12. van Wingerden S, van Wilsem J, Johnson BD. Offender’s personal circumstances and punishment: Toward a more refined model for the explanation of sentencing disparities. Justice Q. 2016 Aug;33(1):100–133.
  13. 13. Goodenough OR, Tucker M. Law and cognitive neuroscience. Annu Rev Law Soc Sci. 2010 Dec;6:61–92.
  14. 14. Greene J, Cohen J. For the law, neuroscience changes nothing and everything. Philos Trans R Soc Lond B Biol Sci. 2004 Nov 29;359(1451):1775–85. pmid:15590618
  15. 15. Farah MJ. Neuroethics: The ethical, legal, and societal impact of neuroscience. Ann Rev of Psychol. 2012 Jan;63:571–591. pmid:19575613
  16. 16. Mobbs D, Lau HC, Jones OD, Frith CD. Law, responsibility, and the brain. PLoS Biol. 2007 Apr 17;5(4):e103. pmid:17439297
  17. 17. Pyun J. When neurogenetics hurts: examining the use of neuroscience and genetic evidence in sentencing decisions through implicit bias. Calif Law Rev. 2015 Aug 1;103(4):1019–46.
  18. 18. Raine A. From genes to brain to antisocial behavior. Curr Dir Psychol Sci. 2008 Oct 1;17(5): 323–328.
  19. 19. Walker B. When the facts and the law are against you, argue the genes; a pragmatics analysis of genotyping mitigation defenses for psychopathic defendants in death penalty cases. Wash Univ Law Rev. 2013 Jun;90:1779–1818.
  20. 20. Wertz J, Caspi A, Belsky DW, Beckley AL, Arseneault L, Barnes JC, Corcoran DL, Hogan S, Houts RM, Morgan N, Odgers CL. Genetics and crime: Integrating new genomic discoveries into psychological research about antisocial behavior. Psychol Sci. 2018 May;29(5):791–803. pmid:29513605
  21. 21. Cox J, Clark JC, Edens JF, Smith ST, Magyar MS. Jury panel member evaluations of interpersonal-affective traits of psychopathy predict support for execution in a capital murder trial simulation. Behav Sci Law. 2013 Jul-Aug;31:411–428. pmid:23754472
  22. 22. de Brigard F, Mandelbaum E, Ripley D. Responsibility and the brain sciences. Ethical Theory Moral Pract. 2009;12:511–24.
  23. 23. Shariff AF, Greene JD, Karremans JC, Luguri JB, Clark CJ, Schooler JW, Baumeister RF, Vohs KD. Free will and punishment: A mechanistic view of human nature reduces retribution. Psychol Sci. 2014 Jun 10;25(8):1563–1570. pmid:24916083
  24. 24. Aspinwall LG, Brown TR, Tabery J. The double-edged sword: Does biomechanism increase or decrease judges' sentencing of psychopaths? Science. 2012 Aug 17;337(6096):846–849. pmid:22904010
  25. 25. Berryessa CM. Judiciary views on criminal behaviour and intention of offenders with high-functioning autism. J Intellect Disabil Offending Behav. 2015 Apr 10;5(2):97–106. pmid:25866642
  26. 26. Dar-Nimrod I, Heine SJ, Cheung BY, Schaller M. Do scientific theories affect men's evaluations of sex crimes? Aggress Behav. 2011 Sep-Oct;37(5):440–449. pmid:21678431
  27. 27. Haslam N, Kvaale EP. Biogenetic explanations of mental disorder: The mixed blessings model. Curr Dir Psychol Sci. 2015;24(5):399–404.
  28. 28. Jayaratne TE, Gelman SA, Feldbaum M, Sheldon JP, Petty EM, Kardia SL. The perennial debate: Nature, nurture, or choice? Black and white Americans' explanations for individual differences. Rev Gen Psychol. 2009 Mar 1;13(1):24–33. pmid:20072661
  29. 29. Monterosso J, Royzman EB, Schwartz B. Explaining away responsibility: Effects of scientific explanation on perceived culpability. Ethics Behav. 2005 Jan 8;15(2):139–158.
  30. 30. Berryessa CM, Cho MK. Ethical, legal, social, and policy implications of behavioral genetics. Annual Review of Genomics and Human Genetics. 2013 Aug 31;14:515–34. pmid:23452225
  31. 31. Berryessa CM. Judicial stereotyping associated with genetic essentialist biases toward mental disorders and potential negative effects on sentencing. Law Soc Rev. 2019 Mar; 53(1):202–238.
  32. 32. Heiphetz L, Young LL. Can only one person be right? The development of objectivism and social preferences regarding widely shared and controversial moral beliefs. Cognition. 2017 Oct;167:78–90. pmid:27260661
  33. 33. Robbins P, Litton P. Crime, punishment, and causation: The effect of etiological information on the perception of moral agency. Psychol Public Policy Law. 2018 Feb;24(1):118–127.
  34. 34. Scurich N, Appelbaum P. The blunt-edged sword: genetic explanations of misbehavior neither mitigate nor aggravate punishment. J Law Biosci. 2016 Apr 3;3(1):140–57. pmid:27239327
  35. 35. Heyman GD, Gelman SA. Beliefs about the origins of human psychological traits. Dev Psychol. 2000 Sep;36(5):663–678. pmid:10976605
  36. 36. Hirschfeld LA. Do children have a theory of race? Cognition. 1995 Feb;54:209–252. pmid:7874877
  37. 37. Tomasello M. Becoming human: A theory of ontogeny. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press; 2019.
  38. 38. Bezdjian S, Raine A, Tuvblad C, Baker AL. The genetic and environmental covariation among psychopathic personality traits, and reactive and proactive aggression in childhood. Child Dev. 2011 Jul-Aug;82(4):1267–81. pmid:21557742
  39. 39. Pinker S. The blank slate. New York, NY: Viking; 2002/2016.
  40. 40. Cohen J. A power primer. Psychol Bull. 1992 July;112:155–159. pmid:19565683
  41. 41. Faul F., Erdfelder E., Lang A.-G., & Buchner A. G*Power 3: A flexible statistical power analysis program for the social, behavioral, and biomedical sciences. Behav Res Methods. 2007 May;39(2), 175–191. pmid:17695343
  42. 42. Berryessa CM. Genetic essentialist biases, stigma, and lack of mitigating impact on punishment decisions. J Law Biosci. 2016 May 4;3(2):359–364.
  43. 43. Keller J. In genes we trust: the biological component of psychological essentialism and its relationship to mechanisms of motivated social cognition. J Pers Soc Psychol. 2005 Apr;88(4):686. pmid:15796668
  44. 44. Rangel U, Keller J. Essentialism goes social: Belief in social determinism as a component of psychological essentialism. J Pers Soc Psychol. 2011 Jun;100(6):1056. pmid:21319911
  45. 45. Bastian B, Haslam N. Immigration from the perspective of hosts and immigrants: Roles of psychological essentialism and social identity. Asian J Soc Psychol. 2008 Jun;11(2):127–40.
  46. 46. Graham J, Haidt J, Koleva S, Motyl M, Iyer R, Wojcik SP, Ditto PH. Moral foundations theory: The pragmatic validity of moral pluralism. Adv Exp Soc Psychol. 2013;47:55–130.
  47. 47. Rottman J, Young L. Specks of dirt and tons of pain: Dosage distinguishes impurity from harm. Psychol Sci. 2019 Aug;30(8):1151–1160. pmid:31242081
  48. 48. Young L, Saxe R. When ignorance is no excuse: Different roles for intent across moral domains. Cognition. 2011 Aug;120(2):202–214. pmid:21601839
  49. 49. Chakroff A, Young L. Harmful situations, impure people: An attribution asymmetry across moral domains. Cognition. 2015 Mar;136:30–37. pmid:25490126
  50. 50. Uhlmann EL, Zhu LL. Acts, persons, and intuitions: Person-entered cues and gut reactions to harmless transgressions. Soc Psychol Personal Sci. 2014;5(3):279–285.
  51. 51. Nagel T. Moral luck. In: Mortal questions. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press; 1979. p. 24–38.
  52. 52. Young L, Nichols S, Saxe R. Investigating the neural and cognitive basis of moral luck: It’s not what you do but what you know. Rev Philos Psychol. 2010 Sep;1(3):333–349. pmid:22558062
  53. 53. Young L, Cushman F, Hauser M, Saxe R. The neural basis of the interaction between theory of mind and moral judgment. Proc Natl Acad Sci U S A. 2007 May 15;104(20):8235–40. pmid:17485679
  54. 54. Siegel JZ, Crockett MJ, Dolan RJ. Inferences about moral character moderate the impact of consequences on blame and praise. Cognition. 2017 Oct;167:201–211. pmid:28527671
  55. 55. Tannenbaum D, Uhlmann EL, Diermeier D. Moral signals, public outrage, and immaterial harms. J Exp Soc Psychol. 2011 Nov;47(6):1249–1254.
  56. 56. Appelbaum PS, Scurich N. Impact of behavioral genetic evidence on the adjudication of criminal behavior. J Am Acad Psychiatry Law. 2014;42(1):91. pmid:24618524
  57. 57. Cheung BY, Heine SJ. The double-edged sword of genetic accounts of criminality: Causal attributions from genetic ascriptions affect legal decision making. Pers Soc Psychol Bull. 2015 Dec;41(12):1723–1738. pmid:26498975
  58. 58. Gromet DM, Darley JM. Retributive and restorative justice: Importance of crime severity and shared identity in people’s justice responses. Aust J Psychol. 2009 May;61(1):50–7.
  59. 59. Myers C. Encouraging allocution at capital sentencing: A proposal for use immunity. Columbia Law Rev. 1997;97:787–818.