Figures
Abstract
From behavioral sciences to biology to quantum mechanics, one encounters situations where (i) a system outputs several random variables in response to several inputs, (ii) for each of these responses only some of the inputs may “directly” influence them, but (iii) other inputs provide a “context” for this response by influencing its probabilistic relations to other responses. These contextual influences are very different, say, in classical kinetic theory and in the entanglement paradigm of quantum mechanics, which are traditionally interpreted as representing different forms of physical determinism. One can mathematically construct systems with other types of contextuality, whether or not empirically realizable: those that form special cases of the classical type, those that fall between the classical and quantum ones, and those that violate the quantum type. We show how one can quantify and classify all logically possible contextual influences by studying various sets of probabilistic couplings, i.e., sets of joint distributions imposed on random outputs recorded at different (mutually incompatible) values of inputs.
Citation: Dzhafarov EN, Kujala JV (2013) All-Possible-Couplings Approach to Measuring Probabilistic Context. PLoS ONE 8(5): e61712. https://doi.org/10.1371/journal.pone.0061712
Editor: Gerardo Adesso, University of Nottingham, United Kingdom
Received: October 22, 2012; Accepted: March 13, 2013; Published: May 6, 2013
Copyright: © 2013 Dzhafarov, Kujala. This is an open-access article distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution License, which permits unrestricted use, distribution, and reproduction in any medium, provided the original author and source are credited.
Funding: This work is supported by NSF grant SES-1155956 (www.nsf.gov). The funder had no role in study design, data collection and analysis, decision to publish, or preparation of the manuscript. No additional external funding has been received for this study.
Competing interests: The authors have declared that no competing interests exist.
Introduction
Consider a system with two inputs, , and two random outputs, , about which it is assumed that is not influenced by , nor by . A necessary condition for this selectivity of influences is marginal selectivity [1]: changes in the values of do not influence the distribution of , and analogously for and . Let, for example, both inputs and outputs be binary: , , and attain values and each. Denoting by and the two outputs conditioned on (), the distribution of is described by the joint probabilities (summing to 1) in the matrix(1)Assuming all four combinations are possible, marginal selectivity in this example means(2)for all .
The assumption of selective influences, however, is stronger. It requires that the joint distribution of the two outputs satisfies, for all ,(3)where stands for “has the same distribution as,” are some functions, and is a source of randomness that does not depend on [2]–[8]. In our example (1) this means(4)In the quantum mechanical context (see below) is interpreted as “hidden variables.” Such a representation may or may not exist when marginal selectivity is satisfied. For instance, the latter is satisfied in the following four distributions,(5)It can be shown, however, that no representation (3) here is possible as the joint probabilities violate the Bell/CHSH inequalities considered below (Section 1 of Theory and Text S1). At the same time, a representation in the form of (3) is possible for the similar distributions(6)One can think of and in (5) and (6) as being involved in different kinds of probabilistic context for the “direct” dependence of, respectively, on and on .
We propose a principled way of quantifying and classifying conceivable contextual influences, whether within or outside the scope of (3). Our approach is neutral with respect to such issues as causality or what distinguishes direct influences from contextual. We merely accept as a given a diagram of direct input-output correspondences (e.g., ) and study the joint distribution of the outputs at all possible values of the inputs. The interpretation of the diagram is irrelevant insofar as it is compatible with the observed pattern of marginal selectivity: as changes while remains fixed, the distribution of does not change, and as changes while remains fixed, the distribution of does not change. Note that the distribution of may but does not have to change in response to changes in , and analogously for and .
Our approach is maximally general in the sense of applying to arbitrary sets of inputs and outputs (see Section 5 of Theory). To demonstrate it by detailed computations, however, we focus primarily on binary influencing binary ; and even more narrowly, on the “homogeneous” case with the two values of both and equiprobable at all values of the inputs (),(7)Marginal selectivity then is satisfied trivially (because all marginal distributions are fixed).
The example focal for this paper is Bohm's version of the Einstein-Podolsky-Rosen paradigm (EPR/B) [9]: a quantum mechanical system consisting (in the simplest case) of two entangled spin particles separated by a space-like interval (see Fig. 1). The two inputs here are spin measurements on these particles: input has two values corresponding to spin axes chosen for one particle, and input has two values corresponding to spin axes for another particle. The two outputs are spin values recorded: having chosen axes and , , one records for the first particle and for the second, each being a random variable with values and . (Note that the spins of a given particle along two different axes are noncommuting (see Text S2), because of which if one spin value is determined precisely, +1 or −1, the other one has a nonzero uncertainty. This means that considered as measurements yielding precise values of spins are mutually exclusive, and this is the reason can be viewed as values of a single input ; and analogously for [10], [11].) Marginal selectivity (2) in this context is known under a variety of other names, such as “parameter independence” and “physical locality” [12]. We confine ourselves to the case (7), with the two spin values +1 and −1 being equiprobable for both and .
Schematic representation of two spin- particles, e.g., electrons, in the singlet state (represented by in quantum-mechanical notation) running away from each other. The directions and are detector settings for spin measurements (in our language, inputs). The measured spins and (outputs) in these directions are shown by rotation arrows: one direction of rotation (say, clockwise) represents “spin-up” in one particle and “spin-down” in the other. By the quantum theory, for any , (equivalently, expected value of is ). The two measurements are made simultaneously (in some inertial frame of reference).
Formally equivalent situations are abundant in behavioral and social sciences [8], [13]–[17], where the issue of selective influences was initially introduced in [18], [19], in the context of information processing architectures. An example of a system here (from our laboratory) can be a human observer who adjusts a visual stimulus until it matches in appearance another, “target” visual stimulus. Let the latter be characterized by two properties, and (e.g., amplitudes of two Fourier-components), each varying on two levels, and . Denoting by and the corresponding properties (amplitudes) of the adjusted stimulus in response to , we define a binary random output as having the value “high” or “low” according as the variable is above or below the median of its distribution; output is defined from analogously. Marginal selectivity in the form (7) is ensured here by construction.
In an example from a biological domain and could be activity levels of two neurons tuned to two stimulus properties, and , respectively. Making and vary on two levels each and defining with respect to the medians of by the same rule as above, we get precisely the same mathematical formulation.
The formal equivalence of these three examples should by no means be interpreted as a hint at their physical affinity. Unlike in the EPR/Bohm paradigm, no physical laws prohibit the activity level of a neuron tuned to stimulus property from being affected by stimulus property . Similarly, the amplitude of the first Fourier component of the adjusted stimulus in the second example may very well be affected by the amplitude of the second Fourier component of the target stimulus. Our only claim is that if these “secondary” influences do not change the marginal distributions of and (which in the two examples in question is ensured by the definition of and ), they can be viewed within the framework of a formal treatment that also includes the (physically very different) case of entangled particles.
Theory
1 Forms of context (determinism)
In the following, symbols (possibly with primes) always take on values each, and each of the outputs takes on values with equal probabilities. Representation (3) is equivalent to the existence of a jointly distributed system(8)such that every output pair is distributed as ; in symbols,(9)As this entailsall components of are random variables with equiprobable +1/−1, and (9) reduces to(10)The existence of in (8) satisfying (9) is known as (a special case of) the Joint Distribution Criterion (JDC) [6], [7], [14], [20], [21]. It follows from (3) by(11)Conversely, if (9) holds for some , then one can put and(12)where stands for the “ th member” (in the list of arguments). The JDC is a deep criterion that provides a probabilistic foundation for our understanding of the classical (non)contextuality (or classical determinism in physics). In particular, it immediately follows from the JDC that if representation (3) for exists, the “hidden variables” can always be reduced to a single discrete random variable with possible values (corresponding to the possible values of ).
Using the same notation as above,(13)the JDC in our case (two binary inputs and two binary outputs with equiprobable values) is equivalent to four double-inequalities(14)with , [6], [7]. (See Text S1 for a derivation.) They are often referred to as the Bell/CHSH inequalities (in the homogeneous form), CHSH acronymizing the authors of [4], although the first appearance of these inequalities dates to [5].
The theory of the EPR/B paradigm predicts and experimental data confirm violations of the Bell/CHSH inequalities [22], [23], but quantum mechanics imposes its own constraint on the same linear combinations of probabilities:(15)This constraint is known as the Cirel'son inequalities [24], [25] (see Text S2 for a derivation). Since the class of vectors that satisfy these double-inequalities include those allowed by (14) as a proper subset, it is natural to expect that (15) represents some relaxation, or generalization of the JDC. No such generalization, however, has been previously proposed. Developing one is the main goal of this paper.
This generalization is not confined to quantum mechanical systems. In other (e.g., behavioral) applications, one cannot exclude a priori the possibility of the bounds and in(16)being wider than in (15), or falling between the bounds in (14) and (15), or being more narrow than in (14). One can think of all kinds of other constraints imposed on the possible values of , from confining this vector to one specific value to allowing it to vary freely. The latter (“complete chaos”) is represented by the “no-constraint” constraint(17)with attained if one of is and the rest are zero, and attained if three of are and the remaining one is zero. Recall that we only consider the outputs with equiprobable outcomes, so(18)All these conceivable constraints on the possible values of represent different forms and degrees of contextual influences. It would be unsatisfactory if all these possibilities, whether or not empirically realizable, could not be treated within a unified probabilistic framework including JDC as a special case. We construct such a framework, based on the classical (Kolmogorov's) theory of probability and the probabilistic coupling theory [26].
2 Connections
It is easy to see that for any vector of probabilities one can find a jointly distributed system of +1/−1 variables(19)such that(20)for all . The JDC then amounts to additionally assuming that among all such vectors there is one with(21)and this is the assumption that is rejected by quantum theory in the EPR/B paradigm. Once (21) is explicitly formulated, however, it becomes clear that it is not the only way of thinking of . Since and occur under mutually exclusive conditions, one cannot identify the distribution of with that of . The latter does not exist as a pair of jointly distributed random variables. There is therefore no privileged pairing scheme for realizations of and ,and zero values for are as acceptable a priori as any other. Analogous considerations apply to and .
Our approach consists in replacing (21) with more general(22)and characterizing the dependence of on by properties of the set of all 4-vectors that are compatible with or imply certain constraints imposed on the vectors . Having adopted a particular diagram of input-output correspondences (in our case, ), we can also say that these sets of characterize the contextual role of for and , respectively.
We call a vector of connection probabilities. The connection probabilities are of a principally non-empirical nature: they are joint probabilities of events that can never co-occur. By contrast, due to (20) the components of are joint probabilities of events that do co-occur, and by observing these co-occurrences the probabilities in can be estimated. To emphasize this distinction we refer to as a vector of empirical probabilities.
To distinguish our approach from other forms and meanings of probabilistic contextualism, e.g., [27], [28], [29], we dub it the “all-possible-couplings” approach. The term “coupling” refers to imposing a joint distribution (say, that of ) on random variables that otherwise are not jointly distributed ( and ). For a rigorous and general discussion of couplings and connections see Section 5.
3 Extended Linear Feasibility Polytope (ELFP)
ELFP is the set of all possible for which there exists a vector in (19) with jointly distributed components such that (20) holds, and, in accordance with (22),(23)for all . The existence of such an means the existence of a probability vector consisting of the joint probabilities(24). Let denote the component vector consisting of 24 empirical probabilities(25)and 24 connection probabilities(26).
Define a Boolean matrix whose rows are enumerated in accordance with components of (i.e., by equalities , , or ) and columns in accordance with components of (i.e., by equalities ). An entry of contains 1 if and only if the corresponding random variables in the enumerations of its row and its column have the same values: e.g., if a row is enumerated by and a column by , then their intersection contains 1 if and only if .
It is easy to see that exists if and only if(27)for some vector (componentwise) of probabilities. The vectors for which such a exists are exactly those within the polytope whose vertices are the columns of the matrix . The term ELFP is due to this construction extending that of the linear feasibility test in [10]. This test, among other applications, is the most general way of extending the Bell/CHSH criterion to an arbitrary number of particles, spin axes, and spin quantum numbers [10], [11], [30]–[32]. Its application to binary inputs/outputs (not necessarily with equiprobable outcomes) is shown in Text S1.
To describe ELFP by inequalities on , we introduce the 16-component sets(28) and denote the subsets of with, respectively, even (0,2, or 4) and odd (1 or 3) number of signs; and are defined analogously. ELFP is described by(29)(see Text S3).
4 All, Fit, Force, and Equi sets
Let denote any constraint (e.g., inequalities) imposed on . Our approach consists in characterizing this constraint by solving the following four problems:
- Find the set of all with subject to : i.e., if and only if(30)
- Find the set of connection vectors that fit (are compatible with) all empirical probability vectors satisfying : i.e., if and only if(31)
- Find the set of that force all compatible empirical probability vectors to satisfy : i.e., if and only if(32)
- Find the set of for which an empirical probability vector satisfies if and only if is in the ELFP set: i.e., if and only if(33)Clearly,
To illustrate, we focus on the following four benchmark constraints. The no-constraint, or “complete chaos” situation is given by(34)equivalent to (17). The quantum mechanical constraint is given by(35)equivalent to (15). The “classical” constraint is given by(36)equivalent to the Bell/CHSH inequalities (14). Finally, we consider the constraint(37)For all constraints except for the sets All, Fit, Force, and Equi are as shown in Table 1 (for derivations see Text S4).
Thus, is the set of all such that : if an is in this set, then any (with no constraints) is compatible with it. is characterized by : if an is in this set, then all compatible with it satisfy . is the set of all such that contains : for any such an , a is compatible with it if and only if it satisfies .
For each of these sets we compute , its volume normalized by that of , with being the dimensionality of the set (Fig. 2). Thus, the defining property of , , is satisfied if and only if either all are , or they all are , or two of them are and two . Hence . For nonzero volumes, the derivation is described in Text S4. Each panel of Fig. 2 can be viewed as a “profile” of the corresponding constraint. Each of the first three volumes in a panel can be viewed as characterizing the “strictness” of a constraint, in three different meanings. The intuition of a stricter constraint is that it corresponds to a smaller , larger , and smaller . Characterizing constraints imposed on empirical probabilities by multidimensional volumes is not a new idea [33], but our computations are different: they are aimed at sets of nonempirical connection probabilities in relation to constraints imposed on empirical probabilities.
Profiles for constraints chaos, quant, and class.
The constraint has to be handled separately. Clearly, . is described by(38)and is a polynomial function of and , these two quantities forming the triangle . The polynomial and its values are shown in Fig. 3 (see Text S5, for computational details). is clearly empty, hence so is .
is shown as a function of and . The possible pairs form the triangle , and , where if and otherwise.
5 All-possible-couplings approach on the general level
We show here how the approach presented so far generalizes to arbitrary sets of inputs and random outputs. We use the term sequence to refer to any indexed family (a function from an index set into a set), with index sets not necessarily countable. We present sequences in the form , , or . A random variable is understood most broadly, as a measurable mapping between any two probability spaces. In particular, any sequence of jointly distributed random variables is a random variable. For brevity, we omit an explicit presentation of probability spaces and distributions. In all other respects the notation and terminology closely follow [15], [11].
An input is a set of elements called input values. Let be a sequence of inputs. A treatment is a sequence that belongs to a nonempty set (so that for all ). If , , and , then and is the restriction of to , i.e., the sequence .
An output is a random variable. Let be a sequence of outputs such that
- is a random variable for every , i.e., the random variables across all possible possess a joint distribution;
- if , , and , then .
Property 2 is (complete) marginal selectivity [8]. is called an empirical random variable, and is the sequence of empirical random variables.
Remark 1. The interpretation is that for every , each may “directly” influence but no other output in . The fact that inputs in and outputs in an empirical random variable are in a bijective correspondence is not restrictive: this can always be achieved by an appropriate grouping of inputs and (re)definition of treatments [10].
Remark 2. The special case considered in the previous sections corresponds to ,(39)(40)and (abbreviating as and as )(41)where each is a binary random variable with .
Given a sequence of empirical random variables , a sequence of random variables(42)(not necessarily jointly distributed) is called a connecting set for if each is a coupling for(43)where . This means that is a random variable of the form(44)with(45)for all such that . is called an connection. The indexation in is to ensure that if , then and are stochastically unrelated. An identity connection is one with for any .
Remark 3. It is generally convenient not to distinguish identically distributed connections. By abuse of language, the distribution of (or some characterization thereof) can also be called connection. We used this language in the previous sections when we represented connections (without introducing them explicitly) by probabilities and called a connection vector. See Remark 4.
A jointly distributed sequence(46)is called an Extended Joint Distribution Sequence (EJDS) for if for any and any ,(47)where , and(48)for any .
Remark 4. For the special case considered in the previous sections, a connecting set for is (conveniently replacing , , and with , , and , respectively)(49)such that(50)for . An EJDS for is a random variable (using analogous abbreviations)(51)such that(52)and(53)for . In the previous sections each was represented by and each by .
An EJDS for reduces to the Joint Distribution Criterion set (JDC set) of the theory of selective influences [11], [14] if all connections in are identity ones. Note that no connection has an empirical meaning: for distinct , the variables and corresponding to and do not have an empirically observable (or theoretically privileged) pairing scheme.
Let be any set whose elements are sequences of empirical random variables . can be viewed as the set of all possible empirical random variables satisfying certain constraints. We define the sets AllX, FitX, ForceX, and EquiX as follows:
- AllX is the set of all pairs such that(54)
- FitX is the set of all such that(55)
- ForceX is the set of all such that(56)
- that is, if and only if(57)
The all-possible-couplings approach in the general case consists in characterizing any (interpreted as a type of contextuality or determinism) by AllX, FitX, ForceX, and EquiX. A straightforward generalization of this approach that might be useful in some applications is to replace in all definitions with a subset of , or several subsets of tried in turn. Thus one might consider connections involving only particular (e.g., only singletons), or one might require that some of the connections are identity ones.
Conclusion
The essence of the proposed mathematical framework is as follows. We consider all possible couplings for empirically observed vectors of random outputs. In the case of two binary inputs/outputs these vectors are pairs(58)the couplings for them have the form (19), with the coupling relation (20). We assume that the joint distributions (in our case described by pairwise joint probabilities) of the empirically observed are subject to a certain constraint, given to us by substantive considerations outside the scope of our approach: for instance, if a system consists of entangled particles, a constraint, say (15), is derived from the quantum theory. Due to (20), the constraint is imposed on(59)We investigate then the unobservable “connections”, the subvectors of the components of that correspond to outputs obtained at mutually exclusive values of the inputs (i.e., never co-occurring). In our case these are the pairs(60)corresponding to, respectively,(61)We then characterize the constraint imposed on the empirical pairs (59) by describing the “fitting” or “forcing” (or both “fitting and forcing”) distributions of the unobservable connections (60). By fitting distributions of (60) we mean those that are compatible with any (59) subject to the constraint in question, the compatibility meaning that all these eight pairs can be embedded into a single (with jointly distributed components). By forcing distributions of (60) we mean those that are compatible with (59) only if the latter are subject to the given constraint.
The value of this approach is in providing a unified language for speaking of probabilistic contextuality. At the cost of greater computational complexity but with no conceptual complications the computations involved in our demonstration of the all-possible-couplings approach can be extended to more general cases: arbitrary marginal probabilities (satisfying marginal selectivity), nonlinear constraints, and greater numbers of inputs, outputs, and their possible values. The language for a completely general theory, involving unrestricted (not necessarily finite) sets of inputs, outputs, and their values, is presented in Section 5 of Theory.
Supporting Information
Text S4.
Computations for , , and constraints.
https://doi.org/10.1371/journal.pone.0061712.s004
(PDF)
Author Contributions
Conceived the mathematical theory: ED. Designed the software used in analysis: JK. Wrote the paper: ED JK.
References
- 1. Townsend JT, Schweickert R (1989) Toward the trichotomy method of reaction times: Laying the foundation of stochastic mental networks. J Math Psych 33: 309–327.
- 2. Bell J (1964) On the Einstein-Podolsky-Rosen paradox. Physics 1: 195–200.
- 3. Bell J (1966) On the problem of hidden variables in quantum mechanics. Rev Modern Phys 38: 447–453.
- 4. Clauser JF, Horne MA, Shimony A, Holt RA (1969) Proposed experiment to test local hiddenvariable theories. Phys Rev Lett 23: 880–884.
- 5. Clauser JF, Horne MA (1974) Experimental consequences of objective local theories. Phys Rev D 10: 526–535.
- 6. Fine A (1982) Joint distributions, quantum correlations, and commuting observables. J Math Phys 23: 1306–1310.
- 7. Fine A (1982) Hidden variables, joint probability, and the Bell inequalities. Phys Rev Lett 48: 291–295.
- 8. Dzhafarov EN (2003) Selective influence through conditional independence. Psychom 68: 7–26.
- 9. Bohm D, Aharonov Y (1957) Discussion of experimental proof for the paradox of Einstein, Rosen and Podolski. Phys Rev 108: 1070–1076.
- 10. Dzhafarov EN, Kujala JV (2012) Selectivity in probabilistic causality: Where psychology runs into quantum physics. J Math Psych 56: 54–63.
- 11. Dzhafarov EN, Kujala JV (2012) Quantum entanglement and the issue of selective influences in psychology: An overview. Lect Notes in Comp Sci 7620: 184–195.
- 12. Cereceda J (2000) Quantum mechanical probabilities and general probabilistic constraints for Einstein-Podolsky-Rosen-Bohm experiments. Found Phys Lett 13: 427–442.
- 13. Kujala JV, Dzhafarov EN (2008) Testing for selectivity in the dependence of random variables on external factors. J Math Psych 52: 128–144.
- 14. Dzhafarov EN, Kujala JV (2010) The Joint Distribution Criterion and the Distance Tests for selective probabilistic causality. Front Quant Psych Meas 1: 151 .
- 15. Dzhafarov EN, Kujala JV (in press) Order-distance and other metric-like functions on jointly distributed random variables. Proc Amer Math Soc (available as arXiv:1110.1228v3 [math.PR])..
- 16. Dzhafarov EN, Schweickert R, Sung K (2004) Mental architectures with selectively influenced but stochastically interdependent components. J Math Psych 48: 51–64.
- 17. Schweickert R, Fisher DL, Goldstein WM (2010) Additive factors and stages of mental processes in task networks. J Math Psych 54: 405–414.
- 18. Sternberg S (1969) The discovery of processing stages: Extensions of Donders' method. In W.G. Koster (Ed.), Attention and Performance II. Acta Psych 30: 276–315.
- 19. Townsend JT (1984) Uncovering mental processes with factorial experiments. J Math Psych 28: 363–400.
- 20. Suppes P, Zanotti M (1981) When are probabilistic explanations possible? Synthese 48: 191–199.
- 21.
Suppes P (2002) Representation and Invariance of Scientific Structures (CSLI, Stanford) pp. 332–351.
- 22. Aspect A, Grangier P, Roger G (1981) Experimental tests of realistic local theories via Bell's theorem. Phys Rev Lett 47: 460–463.
- 23. Aspect A, Grangier P, Roger G (1982) Experimental realization of Einstein-Podolsky-Rosen-Bohm gedankenexperiment: A new violation of Bell's inequalities. Phys Rev Lett 49: 91–94.
- 24. Cirel'son BS (1980) Quantum generalizations of Bell's inequality. Lett Math Phys 4: 93–100.
- 25. Landau LJ (1987) On the violation of Bell's inequality in quantum theory. Phys Lett A 120: 54–56.
- 26.
Thorisson H (2000) Coupling, Stationarity, and Regeneration. New York: Springer.
- 27. Laudisa F (1997) Contextualism and nonlocality in the algebra of EPR observables. Phil Sci 64: 478–496.
- 28. Khrennikov AYu (2008) EPR-Bohm experiment and Bell's inequality: Quantum physics meets probability theory. Theor Math Phys 157: 1448–1460.
- 29.
Khrennikov AYu (2009) Contextual Approach to Quantum Formalism. Fundamental Theories of Physics 160. Dordrecht: Springer.
- 30.
Pitowsky I (1989) Quantum Probability–Quantum Logic. Lect. Notes in Phys. 321. Heidelberg: Springer.
- 31. Peres A (1999) All the Bell inequalities. Found Phys 29: 589–614.
- 32. Basoalto RM, Percival IC (2003) BellTest and CHSH experiments with more than two settings. J Phys A: Math & Gen 36: 7411–7423.
- 33. Cabello A (2005) How much larger quantum correlations are than classical ones. Phys Rev A 72: 12113 1–5.