Skip to main content
Advertisement
  • Loading metrics

Phylogenetic Diversity Theory Sheds Light on the Structure of Microbial Communities

  • James P. O'Dwyer ,

    jodwyer@santafe.edu

    Affiliations Santa Fe Institute, Santa Fe, New Mexico, United States of America, Institute for Ecology and Evolution, University of Oregon, Eugene, Oregon, United States of America

  • Steven W. Kembel,

    Affiliations Institute for Ecology and Evolution, University of Oregon, Eugene, Oregon, United States of America, Départment des sciences biologiques, Université du Québec à Montréal, Montreal, Quebec, Canada

  • Jessica L. Green

    Affiliations Santa Fe Institute, Santa Fe, New Mexico, United States of America, Institute for Ecology and Evolution, University of Oregon, Eugene, Oregon, United States of America

Abstract

Microbial communities are typically large, diverse, and complex, and identifying and understanding the processes driving their structure has implications ranging from ecosystem stability to human health and well-being. Phylogenetic data gives us a new insight into these processes, providing a more informative perspective on functional and trait diversity than taxonomic richness alone. But the sheer scale of high resolution phylogenetic data also presents a new challenge to ecological theory. We bring a sampling theory perspective to microbial communities, considering a local community of co-occuring organisms as a sample from a larger regional pool, and apply our framework to make analytical predictions for local phylogenetic diversity arising from a given metacommunity and community assembly process. We characterize community assembly in terms of quantitative descriptions of clustered, random and overdispersed sampling, which have been associated with hypotheses of environmental filtering and competition. Using our approach, we analyze large microbial communities from the human microbiome, uncovering significant variation in diversity across habitats relative to the null hypothesis of random sampling.

Author Summary

Microbial diversity analyses have revolutionized our knowledge of the microscopic world, from terrestrial and marine to human and urban environments. This growing field rests on the evolutionary relatedness of organisms, and at its frontier is the inference of ecological processes from phylogenetic diversity. However, the rapidly reducing cost of sequencing means that computational analysis of phylogenetic data is becoming increasingly intractable. We develop a new analytical method to address this issue, providing a computationally-efficient way to compare local phylogenetic diversity to a sample from a regional pool of organisms, under a given ecological process. Our approach has both pragmatic and far-reaching applications. Until now investigators have lacked even an analytical method to compare the diversity of unequally-sized communities without throwing data away, while on a deeper level our theory provides a new framework for connecting phylogenetic data to a wide range of ecological processes. As an application of our approach, we use our methods to distinguish between random, clustered and overdispersed sampling for human microbiome habitats. Finally, we identify a new, phylogenetic analogue of the widely used taxonomic measure of diversity, the Species Abundance Distribution, and we find that it has consistent behavior across microbiome habitats.

Introduction

Microbial ecology has been advancing at a rapid pace, but understanding the processes driving microbial community structure remains a challenge [1]. The first step towards identifying these processes has been to document microbial biodiversity, and the use of phylogenetic methods has been stimulated by the abundance of genomic data harvested from microbial communities [2]. Phylogenetic measures of diversity have been proposed as a more accurate representation than taxonomic diversity of community trait and functional diversity, and are therefore a potentially more relevant starting point for quantifying and understanding microbial communities [3]. Phylogenetic approaches have been used to quantify microbial diversity along environmental [4] and elevational gradients [5], [6], across distinct habitat types [7][10] and for different experimental treatments, for habitats ranging from marine and freshwater, to soil, indoor and outdoor air, to the human body [11].

Despite this success in documenting patterns of phylogenetic diversity in a broad range of contexts, our ability to translate these patterns into processes has been hampered by a lack of phylogenetic theory. The difficulty in formulating quantitative hypotheses impacts even the simplest of questions: which of two microbial communities is more phylogenetically diverse? If one community is larger than the other, we cannot answer this basic question without a theoretical hypothesis for the way we expect phylogenetic diversity to increase with community size. More generally, the lack of quantitative, analytical theory has made it difficult to address the relative importance of ecological processes of environmental selection, competition, dispersal and stochasticity in a given community. We have qualitative hypotheses and computational approaches to assess the impact of these processes, but there is no overarching, analytical framework within which to compare them.

Phylogenetic theory can address both of these issues: the pragmatic problem of comparing phylogenetic diversity in different communities, and the larger question of inferring ecological processes from phylogenetic patterns. In this manuscript we develop a way to cast many different assembly processes in a common framework, centering around the comparison of a local community of co-occuring organisms with a sample from a regional, metacommunity of organisms. We draw from the sampling theory of taxonomic diversity [12][14] and our analysis rests on a new way of characterizing a metacommunity phylogenetic tree, which we term the Edge-length Abundance Distribution. This distribution is a new phylogenetic analogue of the classic taxonomic Species Abundance Distribution.

As a proof-of principle application of our framework, we focus on publicly-available human microbiome data [11] and explore three questions centering around the comparison of microbiome phylogenetic diversity with a null hypothesis of random sampling from a metacommunity. First we document patterns across different microbiome habitats and different subjects, and identify a power-law pattern for the Edge-length Abundance Distribution. Species Abundance Distributions have been proposed to have a log-normal distribution in many ecological communities [15], [16], including microbial systems [17], and our work puts this observation on a new, phylogenetic footing. Second, we examine the effect of metacommunity scale on distinguishing different community assembly hypotheses [18], [19]. We compare the diversity of body habitats to a null hypothesis of random sampling from two different definitions of the metacommunity, one significantly larger than the other. We see a clear impact of metacommunity size on the phylogenetic diversity of body habitats relative to the null hypothesis. Finally, we address the question of whether the microbiome of a given human subject is consistent with the null hypothesis of random sampling, and find that while whole microbiome diversity for a given subject is typically much lower than a random sample from the metacommunity, this hides a wide range of different behaviors for the distinct habitats within that subject. We think of this as exploring the impact of local community resolution within the human body: different levels of resolution reveal more complexity.

Results

Phylogenetic Diversity Reflects Community Assembly

Phylogenetic Diversity (PD) has been defined as the total branch length connecting all organisms in a phylogenetic tree, and provides a natural phylogenetic analogue of taxonomic diversity [20]. Similarly, the UniFrac distance measure quantifies the overlap in phylogenetic branch length of two communities, and tells us how similar or different those two communities are [21]. PD and UniFrac provide convenient measures of microbial diversity that do not rely on the ability to identify or enumerate microbial species, and are also amenable to exploring phylogenetic versions of classic biogeographical patterns of alpha and beta diversity.

Comparing observed patterns of phylogenetic diversity to the patterns expected under various null models provides both a normalization to take into account the difference in sample sizes across different habitats or treatments [22], [23], and also a connection between patterns of phylogenetic diversity and the processes underlying them. Given information on the evolution of ecologically important traits [24], [25] and the phylogenetic relatedness of organisms in local communities, an ‘ecophylogenetic’ framework can potentially provide insights into the relative importance of processes such as dispersal, competition, filtering, or drift [26][30]. So far, these approaches to evaluating phylogenetic diversity against null models have relied on ‘brute force’ sampling, where a randomizing algorithm is used to sample tips from a phylogenetic tree, and the process is repeated many times to infer expected phylogenetic diversity for a sample of a given size. This approach becomes intractable for large phylogenetic trees, and must also be repeated for each additional hypothesis and sample size.

We have developed a new, analytical approach to address these problems. Our conceptual framework links a local sample of individual organisms, a regional pool or metacommunity, and processes connecting these two scales. This perspective has a long history in ecological theory [31][33], and has been recently advocated as an appropriate framework for the ecology of symbiont systems [34]. Figure 1 outlines the conceptual overview for this local and metacommunity framework, with explicit examples in the context of the human microbiome. Within our framework, the community assembly processes linking these local and regional scales could be either mechanistic, directly drawing on a process such as dispersal; or phenomenological, characterizing general patterns in statistical terms. The phylogenetic diversity literature has most often focused on the latter, comparing observed PD with the hypotheses of random, clustered and overdispersed sampling. We therefore focus on these sampling schemes in this manuscript, but our framework is potentially generalizable to specific community assembly mechanisms such as dispersal limitation [14]. The methods described in this paper have been implemented in software and will be available in version 1.5 of the picante R package [35].

thumbnail
Figure 1. The local community and metacommunity framework casts local biodiversity of coexisting species in terms of a sampling process from a larger reference pool, or metacommunity.

In (A), (B) and (C) we adapt this framework for a microbial community, the human microbiome, for different definitions of the local community and the reference metacommunity. (A) shows microbiota from a single body habitat, thought of as a sample from the pool of microbiota found in the same habitat on different human subjects. (B) shows the same local community, but thought of as a sample from all microbiota across multiple humans. Finally, the local community in (C) is all microbiota from a single human subject, while the metacommunity is again microbiota from multiple habitats across multiple humans.

https://doi.org/10.1371/journal.pcbi.1002832.g001

Expected phylogenetic diversity and variance.

Our central result is an analytical method to obtain the expected phylogenetic diversity of a local sample from a larger community. In the Supplementary Information we derive the following expression for expected phylogenetic diversity, :(1)Each term in the sum includes all clades in the metacommunity tree which have tips. is the probability that a clade with tips will have at least one representative in the sampled tree, and depends on the choice of sampling process and the local community size. The function only depends on the structure of the metacommunity tree, and is defined as the sum of the branch length of all edges with descendent tips. This is a new way to characterize the phylogenetic structure of the metacommunity tree, which we term the Edge-length Abundance Distribution (EAD). We give a description in Figure 2. We also provide an analytical method to compute the variance in sampled PD, discussed in further detail in the Supplementary Information.

thumbnail
Figure 2. The Edge-length Abundance Distribution, , for a community with four individuals.

All edges are labeled by their length, and the table shows the total edge-length summed across all edges with a given number of upstream tips. Number of tips appears in the left column, and the total edge-length associated with that number of tips, , is shown in the right column. For example, the circled edge has length two, and has two tips downstream, and therefore contributes length to .

https://doi.org/10.1371/journal.pcbi.1002832.g002

The EAD plays an identical role in our sampling framework to the Species Abundance Distribution (SAD) in taxonomic sampling theory [12], [13]. But what does this distribution look like? For the human microbiome we give several examples of the EAD across different subjects and habitats in Figure 3 and find that the distribution displays approximately power law behavior. The Species Abundance Distribution has been proposed to take a near-universal log-normal form in microbial communities [17], and our preliminary results suggest that a power-law distribution may be its phylogenetic analogue.

thumbnail
Figure 3. The Edge-length Abundance Distribution (EAD) follows an approximately power-law distribution.

Here we compute the EAD for trees inferred from 16S bacterial microbiome sequences using FastTree [47], for sequences obtained from 7 human subjects across 26 different habitats on a single sample date [11]. On the y-axis is total edge-length summed across all edges with a given number of downstream tips (see Figure 2) and on the x axis is number of tips grouped into bins, a method commonly used in plotting Species Abundance Distributions [15]. (A) Sequences from all individuals across all body habitats (B–D) Sequences taken from different habitats pooled from all seven subjects. (E–F) Sequences taken from a single subject.

https://doi.org/10.1371/journal.pcbi.1002832.g003

Random sampling has frequently been used as a null model in phylogenetic community ecology, but with the disadvantage of needing to take random samples computationally. For a binomial sampling scheme each individual in the metacommunity has the same probability that of appearing in the sampled tree, so that no individual from the regional pool is more or less likely than any other to appear in a local community. This hypothesis leads to the probability(2)that an edge with descendent tips appears in the sampled tree, so that(3)Expected phylogenetic diversity arising from other commonly used sampling schemes can be cast in the same form: given the EAD for a metacommunity we have the expected PD as a function of sample size for a potentially vast range of community assembly processes.

We demonstrate our approach in Figure 4, where we make the choice of a power law function for the Edge-length Abundance Distribution, similar to those seen for the human microbiome communities in Figure 3. Binomial and Poisson sampling both correspond to the local community being formed by random sampling. The binomial case corresponds to sampling without replacement, while Poisson sampling corresponds to sampling with replacement. Negative binomial sampling can be parametrized to characterize either clustered sampling, where nearby tips are more likely to be sampled together, or overdispersed sampling, where sampling across tips is spread more evenly. The appropriate for binomial sampling is given above, while Poisson sampling and negative binomial are as follows:(4)The parameter represents the departure from random sampling, with positive indicating clustered sampling, negative overdispersed sampling, while in the limit of the negative binomial and poisson sampling are equivalent.

thumbnail
Figure 4. Expected PD for a sample taken from a theoretical metacommunity with a power-law Edge-length Abundance Distribution, for various sampling schemes.

As an approximation to the real communities in Figure 3, we take . The resulting expected PD for Binomial sampling is close to a power law as a function of number of tips sampled, with . We show the corresponding result for Poisson sampling, representing sampling with replacement which is identical to the binomial result until sample size becomes large. Finally, we show two negative binomial schemes with different clustering parameters, , (see Supplementary Information). These parameters are consistent with different degrees of phylogenetic clustering, which leads in general to smaller sampled PD for a given number of tips.

https://doi.org/10.1371/journal.pcbi.1002832.g004

For binomial samples from a power-law EAD, we observe a power-law increase in expected PD with sample size, consistent with the power-law increase in expected PD with sample size observed in other kinds of community [36], [37]. Poisson sampling produces an identical pattern up to very large sample sizes where replacement becomes important. Finally, clustered sampling produces a similar pattern with lower overall PD for a given sample size.

Expected phylogenetic -diversity: unequal sample size increases UniFrac.

We can express the expected shared branch length for two local samples as:(5)Again, the EAD appears, but now we have multiple probabilities and corresponding to the probability that a clade with tips has at least one individual in local community or . Under binomial sampling with probability of each tip being sampled we have:(6)It is more common to compute the unique fraction of branch length for two samples, known as the UniFrac distance, which depends on both this shared branch length, but also on total combined branch length across both samples. Identical samples have no unique branch length, and a Unifrac score of zero, while samples with no branch length in common have a UniFrac score of one.

In one sense UniFrac distance is already normalized: the UniFrac distance of two equally-sized, high diversity communities can be consistently compared with the score for two equally-sized low-diversity samples. What cannot be compared is the UniFrac distance of pairs of differently-sized samples. While the potential impact of unequal sample sizes on computing UniFrac distances has previously been recognized, a common solution has been to subsample [7] all samples down to the smallest size, with the drawback that some data is thrown out.

We can avoid this if we have a normalization for how UniFrac changes with unequal sample sizes. We use our sampling framework to normalize shared and total branch length to provide this normalization. In Figure 5 we plot this result, based on random, binomial sampling from a simulated metacommunity with power law EAD. We find that unequally-sized samples typically have a greater UniFrac normalization than two equally-sized samples from the same regional pool.

thumbnail
Figure 5. Unifrac score normalized for different sample sizes, for two random samples taken from the same theoretical metacommunity.

The score is calculated in terms of expected shared branch length and expected total branch length for the two samples. The black line is for samples of the same size, and colored lines are for various differences in sample size, . As becomes a larger fraction of mean sample size, there is an increasing deviation from the expectation value for equal samples sizes, indicating that an appropriate normalization accounting for differing sample sizes is potentially crucial in computing phylogenetic beta diversity for differently-sized samples.

https://doi.org/10.1371/journal.pcbi.1002832.g005

Human Microbiome, Scale and Resolution

The human body is host to multiple microbial communities, whose combined total outnumbers our own cells by at least a factor of 10 [11], and a community ecology perspective may be essential for a full understanding of the impact of the human microbiome on human health [38]. We now apply our framework to such microbial communities, collected from 7 human subjects across 26 distinct habitats. This data provides an ideal testing ground to demonstrate the utility of our theoretical framework: the largest metacommunity tree we sample from has tips, each tip representing an individual sequence sampled in the study, which would render computational null model approaches intractable. Also, the different community types, subjects and scales allow us to address how our community assembly hypotheses depend on the choice of local community and metacommunity.

Comparing local community phylogenetic diversity with a null model of community assembly.

We now focus on the deviation of microbiome communities from randomly assembled communities. The reason that random sampling is such a crucial baseline is that it lies between two distinct phylogenetic community assembly processes: local communities with lower PD than random are phylogenetically clustered, a signature of environmental filtering, while local communities with higher than random PD are phylogenetically overdispersed, indicating competitive interactions. The true relationship between clustering and overdispersion and these ecological mechanisms is likely more complicated than this simple description [39], [40], but it is a useful starting point [27].

To evaluate the structure of a local community with respect to a given community assembly hypothesis, we need to make an assumption about the pool of individuals or taxa that this local community can draw on: the metacommunity. The ‘true’ regional pool of organisms that a given habitat from a given subject draws upon is difficult to define unambiguously, and so our approach is to allow for various definitions of the metacommunity, and examine the sensitivity of our results on these definitions. This relevance of metacommunity definition has been highlighted before [18], where it has been shown that different metacommunity sizes can lead to different conclusions about the most important ecological mechanisms structuring local communities, and our approach allows us to explore this issue for large microbial metacommunities. Secondly, we also investigate the effect of local community resolution on community assembly hypotheses: how does dividing a local community into smaller, sub-communities impact our understanding of community assembly. In particular we focus on grouping together distinct habitats to form the whole microbiome for a given subject, versus looking at habitats individually, and the effect of these two choices on our conclusions about community assembly.

First, we find that PD increases as a power-law function of sample size. Our definition of a local community is all reads sampled from a single habitat, from a single subject on a single sample day. We plot the results for three habitats in Figure 6, for two different definitions of the metacommunity: (1) all sampled reads from that habitat, across all subjects, and (2) all sampled reads from all habitats, across all subjects. We note the behavior of expected PD, the solid lines in Figure 6: expected phylogenetic diversity as a function of sample size is close to a power law: this is precisely what we would expect for random sampling from a power-law EAD, just as we saw in Figure 3.

thumbnail
Figure 6. Changing metacommunity scale can change whether samples appear clustered or overdispersed.

We show a comparison of actual PD with expected PD under random sampling for three habitats: nose, hair and forehead. Solid lines represent expected PD from random sampling as a function of expected number of tips, dashed lines represent an upper bound on the 95% confidence interval computed using the variance in sampled PD (see Supplementary Information). Points represent actual PD from each of seven human subjects on one sampling day, with subjects labeled by a letter (M or F indicating male or female) and an identifying number. On the top row the reference metacommunity is all reads from that specified habitat, pooled across all seven subjects, and on the bottom row the metacommunity is all sampled reads across all subjects and all habitats. Our central conclusion is that while most samples are consistent with phylogenetic clustering, irrespective of the metacommunity, a minority of communities are consistent with overdispersed sampling from the smaller metacommunity, but clustered sampling from the larger.

https://doi.org/10.1371/journal.pcbi.1002832.g006

Next, we see that larger metacommunities make local samples more likely to appear clustered. There are clear differences between these two example habitats in terms of the range of PD across subjects. For metacommunity (1) we see that most samples are phylogenetically clustered, but several of them are overdispersed. In contrast, from metacommunity (2) all samples are consistent with phylogenetically-clustered sampling. This demonstrates the importance of metacommunity size on distinguishing between hypotheses of environmental filtering and competitive exclusion.

Finally, increasing Local Community Resolution reveals variation in local clustering and overdispersion. In Figure 7 we address the question of whether the microbiome of a given human subject is consistent with clustered, random, or overdispersed sampling. We consider local communities comprising all reads from a given individual, with metacommunities defined using all reads from all subjects on a single sample date. In Figure 7(B) we plot each subject as a single point, seeing that all individuals are consistent with clustered sampling. In Figure 7(A) we zoom in to one subject, plotting their microbiome PD as a cloud of individual habitats. Plotted as single points there is a significant spread in terms of PD with respect to random sampling, with some local communities overdispersed and some highly clustered.

thumbnail
Figure 7. Increasing local community resolution reveals a diversity of clustered and overdispersed local samples.

We show a comparison of actual PD with expected PD for multiple habitats and subjects. The lefthand panel shows the PD of all habitats sampled from subject F1, with the solid line indicating the expected phylogenetic diversity of a random sample from a metacommunity comprising all reads taken from all subjects, and the dotted line representing an upper bound on the corresponding 95% confidence interval. The right hand panel shows the total branch length for all reads sampled from each subject (again including F1 in black), with solid and dotted lines as on the left hand-side. When local samples are grouped into a single community for each microbiome, all microbiome communities are consistent with clustered sampling. On the other hand, we observe a wide range of variation in habitat PD relative to random sampling.

https://doi.org/10.1371/journal.pcbi.1002832.g007

Discussion

In this manuscript we have developed a new, analytical method to quantify and distinguish different hypothesis for the phylogenetic structure of ecological communities. Our approach centers around a new characterization of phylogenetic tree shape, which we term the Edge-length Abundance Distribution (EAD), and we find that this distribution is analogous and complementary to the Species Abundance Distribution (SAD) in taxonomic sampling theory. We observe that the EAD follows a roughly power-law distribution across a number of communities within the human microbiome. Power-law patterns in the distribution of branch lengths have been observed before in phylogenetic trees [41], but while intriguing, the relevance of these patterns was not clear. What makes this pattern different is that, just like the SAD and taxonomic diversity, the definition of the EAD is not arbitrary: it has an essential role in connecting local and regional diversity. An important next step will be to identify what kinds of ecological mechanisms and constraints can give rise to particular types of Edge-length Abundance Distribution, including approximately power law distributions.

We applied this theoretical framework to investigate whether phylogenetic diversity (PD) of local communities from the human microbiome is greater or less than the expected PD for randomly drawn samples from a metacommunity. Local community PD lower than random has been associated with the hypothesis of environmental filtering, while local community PD greater than random (phylogenetic overdispersion) has been associated with competition and competitive exclusion [27]. Taking as our local communities the set of organisms sampled from a single habitat from a single human subject, we observed a wide range of variation across habitats and across subjects in terms of deviation from the random hypothesis. On the other hand, it is not clear yet how to quantitatively connect these deviations to ecological processes, indicating that sampling schemes with a direct connection to ecological mechanism may in the longer term be more relevant than the phenomenological sampling schemes we have explored in this manuscript.

Our results set the scene for a much more rigorous investigation of these issues, and we see three main future directions. For the first time, our framework has made the phylogenetic analysis of large microbial metacommunities analytically tractable, and we find that metacommunity size is highly relevant in our proof-of-principle analysis of human microbiome communities. This confirms the expectation that our conclusions about community assembly depend crucially on the definition of the metacommunity, and indicates the need for a very careful definition of the metacommunity to fully understand the processes structuring local phylogenetic diversity. Second, we have adapted tools from taxonomic sampling and applied them in a phylogenetic context, but this provides just the first steps towards developing a comprehensive theoretical toolbox for distinguishing hypotheses and predicting patterns. Directly characterizing ecological mechanisms, for example dispersal limitation, in terms of our phylogenetic sampling theory will provide a clearer connection between ecological process and phylogenetic patterns.

Finally, we have focused here on the total phylogenetic diversity of local communities [20]. This is the analogue of looking at total species richness alone as a way to distinguish between different hypotheses. In studies of taxonomic diversity, species abundances have provided a way to distinguish quantitatively between different types of community [15], [16], [42], [43], to extrapolate taxonomic diversity to scales far beyond our samples [17] and to connect taxonomic pattern and mechanistic processes more clearly [16], [33], [44][46] than using species richness alone. We do not yet have the overarching phylogenetic theory with which we can distinguish between environmental selection, competition, dispersal and stochasticity. But the application of our framework with mechanistically-based sampling schemes has the potential to put phylogenetic diversity on this same quantitative footing as taxonomic diversity, potentially allowing us to extrapolate PD from local samples to much larger scales, and to distinguish between different ecological hypotheses more effectively.

Methods

Our methods are integrated into the body of the manuscript, primarily in the Results section. Additional methods and derivations are included in our Supporting Information Text S1.

Supporting Information

Figure S1.

Hierarchical clustering for gut samples. Figure S1 displays hierarchical clustering for gut samples. Distances are defined using the Unifrac metric, but normalized by expectation values corresponding to appropriately-sized random samples from the gut metacommunity.

https://doi.org/10.1371/journal.pcbi.1002832.s001

(PDF)

Text S1.

Additional derivations. Text S1 contains additional details of the methods used to obtain results in the main body of the manuscript. It provides a formal derivation for expected local community phylogenetic diversity from a given metacommunity Edge-length Abundance Distribution. It also provides similar derivations for the variance in expected PD and the expected shared and total branch length for two independent samples from a metacommunity.

https://doi.org/10.1371/journal.pcbi.1002832.s002

(PDF)

Acknowledgments

We thank Helene Morlon for comments on the manuscript.

Author Contributions

Conceived and designed the experiments: JPO SWK JLG. Performed the experiments: JPO SWK JLG. Analyzed the data: JPO SWK JLG. Contributed reagents/materials/analysis tools: JPO SWK JLG. Wrote the paper: JPO SWK JLG.

References

  1. 1. Robinson C, Bohannan BJM, Young V (2010) From structure to function: the ecology of host-associated microbial communities. Microbiol Mol Biol R 74: 453–476.
  2. 2. Pace NR (1997) A molecular view of microbial diversity and the biosphere. Science 276: 734–740.
  3. 3. Nee S, May RM (1997) Extinction and the Loss of Evolutionary History. Science 278: 692–694.
  4. 4. Bryant JA, Stewart FJ, Epply JM, DeLong EF (2012) Microbial community phylogenetic and trait diversity declines with depth in a marine oxygen minimum zone. Ecology 93: 1659–73.
  5. 5. Wang J, Soininen J, He J, Shen J (2012) Phylogenetic clustering increases with elevation for microbes. Environmental Microbiology 4: 217226.
  6. 6. Bryant JA, Lamanna C, Morlon H, Kerkhoff AJ, Enquist BJ, et al. (2008) Microbes on mountainsides: Contrasting elevational patterns of bacterial and plant diversity. Proc Natl Acad Sci 105: 11505–11511.
  7. 7. Casamayor EO, Barberan A (2010) Global phylogenetic community structure and β-diversity patterns in surface bacterioplankton metacommunities. Aquat Microb Ecol 59: 1–10.
  8. 8. Lozupone CA, Knight R (2007) Global patterns in bacterial diversity. Proc Natl Acad Sci 104: 11436–11440.
  9. 9. Fierer N, Bradford MA, Jackson RB (2007) Toward an Ecological Classification of Soil Bacteria. Ecology 88: 1354–1364.
  10. 10. Lauber CL, Hamady M, Knight R, Fierer N (2009) Pyrosequencing-Based Assessment of Soil pH as a Predictor of Soil Bacterial Community Structure at the Continental Scale. App Env Micro 75: 5111–5120.
  11. 11. Costello EK, Lauber CL, Hamady M, Fierer N, Gordon JI, et al. (2009) Bacterial community variation in human body habitats across space and time. Science 326: 1694–7.
  12. 12. Plotkin JB, Muller-Landau HC (2002) Sampling the Species Composition of a Landscape. Ecology 83: 3344–3356.
  13. 13. Green JL, Plotkin JB (2007) A statistical theory for sampling species abundances. Ecol Lett 10: 1037–45.
  14. 14. Etienne RS (2005) A new sampling formula for neutral biodiversity. Ecol Lett 8: 253–260.
  15. 15. Preston FW (1960) Time and space and the variation of species. Ecology 41: 610–627.
  16. 16. May RM (1975). Patterns of species abundance and diversity. In: Cody M, Diamond J, editors. Ecology and Evolution of Communities. Cambridge: Belknap Press. pp. 81–120.
  17. 17. Curtis TP, Sloan WT, Scannell JW (2009) Estimating prokaryotic diversity and its limits. Proc Natl Acad Sci 99: 10494–9.
  18. 18. Swenson NG, Enquist BJ, Pither J, Thompson J, Zimmerman JK (2006) The Problem and Promise of Scale Dependency in Community Phylogenetics. Ecology 87: 2418–2424.
  19. 19. Swenson NG, Enquist BJ, Thompson J, Zimmerman JK (2007) The influence of spatial and size scale on phylogenetic relatedness in tropical forest communities. Ecology 88: 1770–1780.
  20. 20. Faith DP (1992) Conservation evaluation and phylogenetic diversity. Biol Cons 61: 1–10.
  21. 21. Lozupone CA, Knight R (2005) UniFrac: a New Phylogenetic Method for Comparing Microbial Communities. Appl Environ Microbiol 71: 8228.
  22. 22. Schloss P (2008) Evaluating different approaches that test whether microbial communities have the same structure. ISME Journal 2: 265–275.
  23. 23. Ives AR, Helmus MR (2010) Phylogenetic metrics of community similarity. Am Nat 176: E128–E142.
  24. 24. Blomberg SP, Garland T, Ives AR (2003) Testing for phylogenetic signal in comparative data: behavioral traits are more labile. Evolution 57: 717–745.
  25. 25. Cahill JF, Kembel SW, Lamb EG, Keddy PA (2008) Does phylogenetic relatedness influence the strength of com- petition among vascular plants? Perspect Plant Ecol Evol Syst 10: 41–50.
  26. 26. Webb CO, Ackerly DD, McPeek MA, Donoghue MJ (2002) Phylogenies and community ecology. Ann Rev Ecol Syst 33: 475–505.
  27. 27. Mouquet N, Devictor V, Meynard CN, Munoz F, Bersier LF, et al. (2012) Ecophylogenetics: advances and perspectives. Biol Rev Camb Philos Soc 87: 769–785.
  28. 28. Emerson BC, Gillespie RG (2008) Phylogenetic analysis of community assembly and structure over space and time. Trends Ecol Evol 23: 619–630.
  29. 29. Vamosi SM, Heard SB, Vamosi JC, Webb CO (2008) Emerging patterns in the comparative analysis of phylogenetic community structure. Mol Ecol 18: 572–592.
  30. 30. Stegen JC, Lin X, Konopka AE, Fredrickson JK (2012) Stochastic and deterministic assembly processes in subsurface microbial communities. ISME J 6: 1653–64.
  31. 31. MacArthur RM, Wilson EO (1967) The Theory of Island Biogeography. Princeton: Princeton Univ. Press.
  32. 32. Holyoak M, Leibold MA, Holt RD (2005) Metacommunities: spatial dynamics and ecological communities. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
  33. 33. Hubbell SP (2001) The Unified Neutral Theory of Biodiversity and Biogeography. Princeton: Princeton Univ. Press.
  34. 34. Mihaljevic JR (2012) Linking metacommunity theory and symbiont evolutionary ecology. Trends Ecol Evol 27: 323–329.
  35. 35. Kembel SW, Cowan PD, Helmus MR, Cornwell WK, Morlon H, et al. (2010) Picante: R tools for integrating phylogenies and ecology. Bioinformatics 26: 1463–1464.
  36. 36. Morlon H, et al. (2011) Spatial patterns of phylogenetic diversity. Ecol Lett 14: 141–9.
  37. 37. Helmus MR, Ives AR (2012) Phylogenetic diversity area curves. Ecology In press.
  38. 38. Costello EK, Stagaman K, Dethlefsen L Bohannan BJM, Relman DA (2012) The application of ecological theory toward an understanding of the human microbiome. Science 336: 1255–1262.
  39. 39. Valiente-Banuet A, Verdu M (2007) Facilitation can increase the phylogenetic diversity of plant communities. Ecol Lett 10: 1029–1036.
  40. 40. Mayfield MM, Levine JM (2010) Opposing effects of competitive exclusion on the phylogenetic structure of communities. Ecol Lett 13: 1085–1093.
  41. 41. Herrada EA, et al. (2008) Universal scaling in the branching of the tree of life. PLoS One 3: e2757.
  42. 42. Sugihara G (1980) Minimal Community Structure: An Explanation of Species Abundance Patterns. Am Nat 116: 770–787.
  43. 43. Rosenzweig ML (1995). Species Diversity in Space and Time. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  44. 44. Sloan WT, Lunn M, Woodcock S, Head IM, Nee S, et al. (2006) Quantifying the roles of immigration and chance in shaping prokaryote community structure. Environ Microbiol 8: 732–740.
  45. 45. Ofiteru I, Lunn M, Curtis TP, Wells GF, Criddle CS, et al. (2010) Combined niche and neutral effects in a microbial wastewater treatment community. Proc Natl Acad Sci 107: 15345–50.
  46. 46. Jeraldo P, Sipos M, Chia N, Brulc JM, Dhillon AS, et al. (2012) Quantification of the relative roles of niche and neutral processes in structuring gastrointestinal microbiomes. Proc Natl Acad Sci 109: 9692–8.
  47. 47. Price MN, Dehal PS, Arkin AP (2009) FastTree: Computing Large Minimum Evolution Trees with Profiles instead of a Distance Matrix. Mol Biol Evol 26: 1641–1650.