Skip to main content
Advertisement
Browse Subject Areas
?

Click through the PLOS taxonomy to find articles in your field.

For more information about PLOS Subject Areas, click here.

  • Loading metrics

On the Fair Division of Multiple Stochastic Pies to Multiple Agents within the Nash Bargaining Solution

  • Athanasios C. Karmperis ,

    athkarmp@mail.ntua.gr

    Affiliations Sector of Industrial Management and Operational Research, School of Mechanical Engineering, National Technical University of Athens, Athens, Greece, Army Corps of Engineers, Hellenic Army General Staff, Ministry of Defence, Athens, Greece

  • Konstantinos Aravossis,

    Affiliation Sector of Industrial Management and Operational Research, School of Mechanical Engineering, National Technical University of Athens, Athens, Greece

  • Ilias P. Tatsiopoulos,

    Affiliation Sector of Industrial Management and Operational Research, School of Mechanical Engineering, National Technical University of Athens, Athens, Greece

  • Anastasios Sotirchos

    Affiliation Sector of Industrial Management and Operational Research, School of Mechanical Engineering, National Technical University of Athens, Athens, Greece

Abstract

The fair division of a surplus is one of the most widely examined problems. This paper focuses on bargaining problems with fixed disagreement payoffs where risk-neutral agents have reached an agreement that is the Nash-bargaining solution (NBS). We consider a stochastic environment, in which the overall return consists of multiple pies with uncertain sizes and we examine how these pies can be allocated with fairness among agents. Specifically, fairness is based on the Aristotle’s maxim: “equals should be treated equally and unequals unequally, in proportion to the relevant inequality”. In this context, fairness is achieved when all the individual stochastic surplus shares which are allocated to agents are distributed in proportion to the NBS. We introduce a novel algorithm, which can be used to compute the ratio of each pie that should be allocated to each agent, in order to ensure fairness within a symmetric or asymmetric NBS.

Introduction

Over the last decades, effective management of cooperative structures has been of great interest, due to its application to various real life situations. Generally, in all kinds of cooperative structures there is a nonnegative surplus included in the overall return, which may consist of more than one pie. For instance, in a supply chain network with multiple production facilities that produce different products, the manufacturing and distribution costs as well as the unit profits are dissimilar. Another example is a water/power/waste management system that commonly includes the collection and distribution of water/power/waste arising from different sources. In most cases, these multiple pies should be shared among a finite set of agents who receive specific payoffs if they disagree to cooperate, i.e. through the non-cooperative option. Moreover, since a cooperative venture is formed before the actual size of each pie is realized, these pies can be assumed as stochastic variables, i.e. pies with uncertain sizes. In such a stochastic environment with multiple pies and multiple agents, main challenge is to ensure fairness, especially when risk-neutral agents have already reached an agreement for the division of the overall surplus. The subsequent sections of this paper include the review of the related literature, the description of the basic problem, the introduction of a novel computation method and the discussion of possible applications and future research issues.

Solution Concepts in Cooperative Games

More than 2000 years ago, Aristotle in “Nicomachean Ethics” has established the main principle of fairness. He indicates that equals must be treated equally and unequals must be treated unequally, in proportion to relevant similarities and differences [1], [2]. This is a formal principle, which has been applied to all kind of cooperative structures, e.g. equal treatment and proportionality are two general principles of European Union Law.

Cooperative game theory is applied to a finite set of agents, namely grand-coalition, while any subset in which this set can be divided is called coalition [3], and a coalition with just one agent is called singleton. A cooperative game for a grand-coalition N = {1,2,3,…,n}, is either a pair (N, p) and a characteristic function p : 2N → ℜ, with p(Ø) = 0, which represents the collective payoff for a set of agents forming a coalition [4], or a pair (N, c) and a characteristic function c : 2N → ℜ, with c(Ø) = 0 that describes the cost for a set of agents who cooperate in accomplishing a specific task [5]. The solution of the game is a vector x Є ℜN representing the allocation of the overall profit p(N) or cost c(N) to each agent. In general, a nonnegative surplus can be shared with fairness following the equal or proportional sharing methods [6]. In the literature, several papers aim to provide axiomatic characterizations of fair solutions, while a different approach of fairness results in a different solution concept. These are the solution of von Neumann–Morgenstern [7], the Shapley value [8], the core [9], and the Nucleolus [10]. Moreover, alternative axioms are discussed in [6], [11], [12], [13]. However, the most widely applied solution for the cooperative bargaining problem with fixed disagreement payoffs is the Nash-bargaining solution (NBS) [14]. The NBS consists of an axiomatic derivation of the solution for a bargaining game between two agents, who have perfect information [15], [16] and examine to cooperate and share a specific surplus. This solution, which can be easily expanded in more than two agents [17], [18], satisfies a set of axioms: linear invariance and independence of irrelevant alternatives (the solution is preserved under the monotone transformation of the agents’ utility functions or the exclusion of non-selected alternatives from the bargaining set); Pareto-optimality (any change to a different allocation that makes one agent better off will make the other agent worse off); feasibility (the sum of the agents’ allocations does not exceed the shared pie) and symmetry (identical agents receive equal utility allocations). Moreover, the asymmetric NBS is applied to cases with non-identical agents [19], [20].

Surplus Sharing Mechanisms and Bargaining in Stochastic Environment

In recent papers, the fair division of a surplus among risk-averse agents is examined in [21] and several authors analyze the profit-sharing [22], revenue-sharing [23], cost-sharing [24] and cost-revenue sharing [25], [26] mechanisms in cooperative structures. Other surplus division models are applied to supply network formation [27], to decentralized supply chains [28], [29], and to river water [30] and groundwater [31] sharing cases. However, taking into consideration that a surplus sharing mechanism should use risk as driver [32], there is a strong interaction between the divisions of a surplus with the risk allocated to agents. For instance, in [33] is developed an analytic model based on the maximization of the probability that a firm will achieve some given profit target, and in [34] is developed a risk-based process that can be used to compute the range including the win-win funding schemes of partnerships at a predefined level of probability.

As mentioned in [35], the theoretical literature on bargaining in stochastic environment is limited. In particular, few papers examine cases where agents are negotiating over a surplus with uncertain size, i.e. they receive individual surplus shares (called dividends) with uncertain sizes. One of the mostly used techniques for handling uncertainty is the Monte Carlo Simulation (MCS), which takes into account the impact of a set of stochastic variables (inputs) and defines the possible range of the output values graphically expressed as the cumulative probability distribution function [36], [37], [38], [39].

However, a rational investor would like to minimize the probability of the expected losses [40], or/and to maximize the probability of the expected gains. This implies that an allocation with which the probability of being negative an agent’s dividend is high and the probabilities of being negative the opponents’ dividends are low, cannot be considered as fair. In other words, a fair surplus division has to be based not only on the expected values of the agents’ dividends, but also should take into account their standard deviations. If agents agree in a specific sharing scheme of the overall surplus within the NBS, then fairness is achieved when the mean values and the standard deviations of the agents’ dividends are proportional to the NBS. Proportionality implies that when the surplus is divided equally, the expected dividends and their standard deviations should be equal [26]. Specifically, in contrast with [41], which indicates the impossibility of fair risk allocation, in [26] is developed a basic model for the equal profit and risk allocation among agents who examine to cooperate by undertaking parts of the system cost individually and share the remaining costs and revenues. It is proved that when two pies with uncertain sizes are allocated to non-identical agents, there is a finite set of possible solutions that depends on the number of agents. However, this model is limited in cases with two stochastic pies. Herein, we consider a stochastic environment, in which the overall return consists of multiple pies with uncertain sizes and the surplus is not necessarily divided equally, i.e. when agents negotiate and agree in a specific NBS, this solution can be either symmetric with equal payoffs or asymmetric with equal or unequal payoffs [19], [20], [42]. The main objective of this paper is to introduce a novel method that can be used to compute the ratio of each pie that should be allocated to each agent, in order to ensure fairness within a specific NBS. A complete list of the notations used in this paper is presented in Table 1 and the proofs of Theorems and Propositions are shown in Supporting Information Text S1.

Problem Description and Mathematic Formulation

Assumptions.

We consider a finite number of agents indexed by i. Let N = {1,2,3,…,n} denote the grand-coalition of all agents. The following assumptions are used throughout the paper:

  1. Assumption 1. There is complete information among agents, who examine the cooperative option having specific disagreement payoffs. This implies that if they do not reach an agreement, then their payoff vector is : (C1,C2, …,Cn). In this case, the participants’ objectives are partially cooperative, as they aim at reaching an agreement and partially conflicting, because each agent has its own utility function regarding the negotiation outcome [43].
  2. Assumption 2. The different gains and losses that are yielded through cooperation forming a finite set of pies J = {1,2,3,…,m} that is called pie-set. These pies are divisible and should be shared among agents. However, since the grand-coalition is formed before the actual size of each pie is realized, all pies are assumed to be stochastic variables [44]. Specifically, all pies indexed by j follow normal probability distribution functions with specific mean values and variances: , where σj>0 for all pies, µj>0 for pies representing gains and µj<0 for pies representing losses.
  3. Assumption 3. Agents are rational, i.e. each agent should get at least as much as it could obtain through the non-cooperative option. Clearly, the cooperation yields a nonnegative surplus S. That is, the N’s overall return is equal to the sum of agents’ disagreement payoffs plus the surplus S [6]:
  4. Assumption 4. All agents are risk-neutrals, i.e. they are indifferent between the m pies, since they consider only the overall expected return when making investment decisions [38]. In particular, they negotiate over the division of the surplus that is yielded through cooperation and the bargaining outcome is the NBS, which is a vector: representing the expected individual surplus shares (dividends) which are allocated to agents. This is the unique solution that maximizes a function equal to the product of the agents’ utility net gains from cooperation, measured relative to the exogenous disagreement outcome [17], [18], [45].

Axioms.

The allocation of the surplus S that is yielded through cooperation fulfils the following axiom:

  1. Coalitionally rational [46]: This axiom is satisfied when the expected return (sum of expected gains minus the relative losses) is greater than the sum of agents’ disagreement payoffs, i.e. the S’s mean value, denoted by µN, should be positive:

(1)Since all agents are risk-neutrals, they negotiate over the S’s mean value considering their expected dividends (µi). The bargaining outcome is an allocation, i.e. a vector U Є ℜN representing the ratio of the µN that is divided in agent i Є N:(2)

All agents are assumed to be rational and thus the allocation U Є ℜN fulfils the following axiom:

  1. Individually rational: Agent i get at least as much as it could obtain through the non-cooperative option, according to the following inequality:
  2. (3) Linear Invariance and Independence of Irrelevant Alternatives: Since the bargaining outcome is assumed to be the NBS, it has to be linear invariance and independent of irrelevant alternatives. Let F be the feasible set of allocations. If F ‘is obtained from F by multiplying all agents’ utilities by αi, then the solution of the new game is obtained by multiplying each agent’s coordinate in the first solution by αi. Moreover, the solution remains the same for each subset of F that includes the specific solution.
  3. Feasibility and Pareto-Optimality: In order to fulfill the feasibility and Pareto-optimality axioms, the allocation should be efficient, i.e. the sum of expected dividends equals the expected surplus:

(4)Eq (4) ensures feasibility, as the sum of allocations does not exceed the overall surplus. Moreover, inequality (3) and Eq (4) ensure Pareto-optimality, because for any other allocation U’≠ U, with which at least one agent i is better off: Ui’>Ui, and from Eq (2): µii, there will be at least one agent k worse off: Uk’<Uk, and from Eq (2): µkk. Hence, there are no Pareto improvements which can be made in U and the negotiation result is Pareto-Optimal.

Letdenote the ratio of pie j Є J which is allocated to agent i Є N. It is clear that agent’s i expected dividend is: , while her expected overall return is: . Due to the fact that an inefficient allocation of at least one pie j will leave space for renegotiation, we consider the efficient allocation of all pies j Є J,:(5)

  1. Symmetry: On one hand, if all agents are identical (equal disagreement payoffs and symmetric utility functions), then they will agree in the equal allocation of the overall surplus, according to Eq (6):

(6)On the other hand, if agents are non-identical, then the bargaining outcome will be the asymmetric NBS [19]. In the asymmetric NBS, the surplus can be divided either equally fulfilling Eq. (6) [42], or unequally with Ui ≠ Uk for at least two agents i, k Є N.

The axiom of fair division.

In cases where multiple pies should be shared among multiple agents within a symmetric or asymmetric NBS, main challenge is to ensure fairness for the division of the overall surplus [47]. Let Πi denote the individual stochastic surplus share, which is allocated to agent i. This is given from Eq (7):(7)

Taking into consideration that all pies j Є J are normally distributed and the agents’ disagreement payoffs Ci are real numbers, we conclude that the stochastic dividends which are allocated to agents follow normal probability distribution functions: . Moreover, a solution satisfying U consists of the ratios for all i Є N and j Є J. In particular, a solution can be illustrated in a [P]nXm matrix, in which the 1,2,.,n rows denote the agents and the 1,2,.,m columns denote the pies, i.e. each elementrepresents the ratio of pie j which is allocated to agent i:(8)

In this case, the characteristic function of the dividends allocated to all agents within a symmetric or asymmetric NBS can be expressed in Eq (9):(9)

However, fairness is achieved when all these dividends are distributed in proportion to the NBS: , i.e. the expected values of the dividends which are allocated to agents should satisfy:(10)and the dividends’ standard deviations, denoted by σi, should be also proportional to the mean values, according to Eq (11):

(11)In other words, fairness is achieved when the dividends which are allocated to all agents are distributed in proportion to the NBS, fulfilling Eq (12):(12)

Results

Even though most papers dealing with cooperative games use a bottom-up approach examining which coalition of agents can be formed, or how sub-coalitional gains can be allocated in order to secure a sustainable agreement, herein we follow a top-down approach.

Computing Solutions for Fair Surplus Division

A novel approach to compute the ratio of each pie that should be allocated to each agent, in order to ensure that the surplus is divided in proportion to the NBS, is presented in Figure 1. As can be seen, the general method introduced with this paper includes two basic stages, which are following analyzed:

Stage 1: Partition the pie-set J into two nonempty subsets: JA, JB, and the grand-coalition N into two nonempty coalitions NA NB.

Initially, we consider that we have to use the above Eqs (1) to (10), in order to estimate the (n×m) unknowns of a [P]nXm matrix that satisfy the axiom of fairness. However, through the partition of the pie-set J = {1,2,.,m} into two subsets: JA = {1,…,g}, and JB = {g+1,…,m}, with 1≤ g<m, the characteristic function is presented in Eq (13):(13)wheredenote the ratio of the subset JA = {1,…,g} allocated to agent i, anddenote the ratio of the subset JB = {g+1,…,m} allocated to agent i. This implies that the ratios of pie 1, pie 2, …, and pie g, which are allocated to agent i are equal to: , and the ratios of pie g+1, pie g+2, …, and pie m, which are also allocated to agent i are equal to: .

Moreover, through the partition of the grand-coalition N into two coalitions: NA = {1,…, h}, NB = {h+1,…,n}, with 1≤ h<n, we have 4 unknowns, which are the ratios of each subset: JA = {1,…,g} and JB = {g+1,…,m} allocated to each coalition: NA = {1,…, h} and NB = {h+1,…,n}:(14)

Specifically, through the partitions of the pie-set and the grand-coalition into a pair of two nonempty subsets and two nonempty coalitions, the characteristic function (9) is expressed in Eq (15):(15)

Further, we derive the following Theorem 1.

Theorem 1.

For each pair of two coalitions and two subsets that can arise from the partition of the grand-coalition N = {1,.,n} into: NA = {1,.,h}and NB = {h+1,.,n}, (NA U NB = N; NA ∩ NB = Ø) and the partition of the pie-set J = {1,.,m} into: JA = {1,.,g} and JB = {g+1,.,m}, (JA U JB = J; JA ∩ JB = Ø), there is a unique [P] 2×2 matrix: , which ensures fairness within the NBS satisfying Eq (12):

Stage 2: Continuous partitions of the agents’ coalitions for n-1 times.

From Theorem 1, it is clear that through the partition of the coalition NA = {1,.,h} into two nonempty coalitions {1,., f} and {f+1,…,h}, 1≤ f<h, Eq (15) gives:(16)which has a unique [P] 2×2 matrix: satisfying Eq (12) and .

Similarly, through the partition of the coalition NB = {h+1,.,n} in another pair of nonempty coalitions {h+1,., k} and {k+1,…,n}, h+1≤ k<n, Eq (15) gives:(17)which also has a unique [P] 2×2 matrix: satisfying Eq (12) and .

In particular, the partitioning of coalitions into two nonempty coalitions is continued, until eventually all agents form singletons: {1}, {2}, {3},…, {n}, i.e. for n-1 times. Through this process, if we compute the unique [P] 2×2 matrix for each coalition, we can compute the ratio of each subset {1,.,g} and {g+1,.,m} which is allocated to each agent.

Let denote the set of coalitions including agent i, which arise from a specific set of partitions of the grand-coalition N into two nonempty coalitions for n-1 times. For instance, through the continuous partitions of the N = {1,2,3,4,5} within a specific partition set, into: {1} and {2,3,4,5}, and the further partition into {3} and {2,4,5}, and the further partition into {2} and {4,5} and the further partition into {4} and {5}, the sets of coalitions including agents are:

That is, the ratio of each subset of pies ({1,.,g} and {g+1,.,m}), which is allocated to agent i, equals the product of ratios of the coalitions, in which i is included, e.g. for agent 5:

However, the ratio for agent i in each subset of pies {1,…,g} and {g+1,…,m}, equals her ratios in all pies of the specific subset: and .

In other words, through the partition of the pie-set J into two nonempty subsets, and the continuous partitions of all coalitions into a pair of nonempty coalitions for n-1 times (until all agents form singletons), we can compute the ratios of all pies j = 1,2,.,m which are allocated to all agents i = 1,2,.,n. That is, we can compute a specific matrix [P] n×m, which ensures that the agents’ dividends are distributed in proportion to the NBS:

Basic Features

In this section, we present some basic features of the proposed method.

Number of possible partitions of the pie-set.

Let g(m) denote the possible combinations for the partition of the pie-set J into two nonempty subsets. We derive the following Proposition 1.

Proposition 1.

The number of possible partitions of a pie-set J into two nonempty subsets is given from the piecewise Eq (18): (18)

Finite possible [P] n×m matrices for fair surplus division.

However, in each partition of the grand-coalition N into two nonempty coalitions according to the first stage of the proposed method, or any other partition of the agents’ coalitions into two nonempty coalitions according to the second stage, there is no coalition that can be profitably blocked. This implies that there is no constraint considered and any agent can be placed either in the first or the second coalition of each partition, in which the order of agents does not matter. Let f(n) denote the possible combinations for the continuous partitions of coalitions for n-1 times (until all agents form singletons: {1},…,{n}. Taking into consideration that for each partition into two nonempty coalitions there is a unique [P] 2×2 matrix, we derive Theorem 2.

Theorem 2.

The number of possible [P] n×m matrices that ensure fairness for the surplus division within a NBS, is finite and equals the product of the possible partitions of the pie-set into two subsets with the possible partitions of all coalitions of agents into two nonempty coalitions for n-1 times:(19)where:

(19.1) (19.2)

Possible [P] n×m matrices for 2≤ n, m ≤10.

The precise number of possible [P] n×m matrices for 2≤ m, n ≤10, is illustrated in Table 2. As can be seen, this Table presents the numbers of possible matrices for all combinations of: m, n = 2,3,4,., 10. For instance, when there are 7 stochastic pies to be allocated to 5 agents, there are 6615 matrices [P] 5×7 satisfying Eq (12), and when there are 5 stochastic pies to be allocated to 7 agents, there are 155925 matrices [P] 7×5 satisfying Eq (12).

thumbnail
Table 2. Number of possible [P] n×m matrices for fair surplus division.

https://doi.org/10.1371/journal.pone.0044535.t002

Computation Algorithm

In this section we introduce an algorithm, which can be used to compute a [P] n×m matrix that ensures fairness for the division of the overall surplus. This algorithm consists of seven basic steps, which are presented below:

  1. 1. Step 1: Randomly partition the pie-set J into two subsets: {1,…,g} and {g+1,…,m} with 1≤ g<m.
  2. 2. Step 2: Randomly partition the grand-coalition N into two coalitions: {1,…,h} and {h+1,…,n} with 1≤ h<n.
  3. 3. Step 3: Develop a MCS model, in which the Ci, Π j are inputs and the Π{1,.,h}, Π{h+1,.,n} the outputs, according to the following Eqs (20) and (21):

(20) (21)

  1. 4. Step 4: Select a specific value of , and estimate the , in order to fulfill:

(22) (23)

For the that fulfils Eqs (22), (23) run the MCS and estimate σ{1,.,h}, σ{h+1,.,n}. If the following Eq (24) is fulfilled then go the next Step, otherwise examine alternative values of (simply by increasing/decreasing its initial value), until you find the unique elements of a [P] 2×2 matrix: , which fulfils Eq (24):(24)

  1. 5. Step 5: Use the , and return to Step 2, i.e. randomly partition both the {1,…,h} and {h+1,…,n} coalitions into two pairs of nonempty coalitions: {1,…,f}, {f+1,…,h} and {h+1,…,k}, {k+1,…,n}, respectively, and compute the unique ratios: and . Specifically, the 2 to 5 Steps should be followed for n-1 times.
  2. 6. Step 6: Calculate the ratio of each subset {1,…,g} and {g+1,…,m} allocated to each agent, through the product of the ratios of the agent-coalitions in which the agent is included. Moreover, due to the fact that each agent’s ratios are equal in all pies of each subset, illustrate the [P] n×m matrix.
  3. 7. Step 7: In order to verify the results, develop another MCS model, in which the computed [P] n×m, the [Π j] m×1, and the [Ci] n×1 matrices are inputs, and the [Π i] n×1 is the output according to Eq (9):

(9)Run the simulation and estimate: , and, in order to verify that the dividends are allocated to all agents with fairness:

Discussion

Numerical Example

In this section we present a numerical example with the application of the proposed computation algorithm. We consider 4 risk-neutral agents forming a grand-coalition N = {1, 2, 3, 4}. All agents are rational and agree to cooperate having different disagreement payoffs, i.e. through the non-cooperative option they receive: C1 = 2×106, C2 = 5×106, C3 = 3×106, and C4 = 2×106. We examine a general case with non-identical agents and the asymmetric NBS, considering that the symmetric NBS can be included as a special case where agents’ utility functions are symmetric and the disagreement payoffs are equal: C1 = C2 = C3 = C4. There are 5 different pies representing the N’s gains through cooperation, i.e. the pie-set is: J = {1, 2, 3, 4, 5}. Since the grand-coalition is formed before these gains are realized, each pie indexed by j follows a normal probability distribution function with specific mean value (μ j) and standard deviation (σ j), as presented in Table 3. All agents are risk-neutrals implying that they are indifferent between the m pies, as they consider only their expected dividends. Specifically, they negotiate over the expected value of the surplus (μΝ), which is yielded through cooperation. This value is computed with Eq (1):(1)

thumbnail
Table 3. Normal probability distributions of pies (values×106).

https://doi.org/10.1371/journal.pone.0044535.t003

The bargaining outcome is a vector U Є ℜN representing the ratio of the µN that is allocated to agent i. The subsequent sections examine two cases within the asymmetric NBS, which is the payoff that maximizes a weighted product of players' gains over their disagreement payoff.

Asymmetric NBS with unequal divisions.

The first case is the asymmetric NBS where the surplus is divided unequally among agents. We assume that this solution is: U = (U1, U2, U3, U4) = (0.12, 0.25, 0.30, 0.33). Since all pies included in Table 3 should be allocated to all agents with fairness, we want to compute the ratio of each pie that should be allocated to each agent, in order to ensure that the agents’ dividends [Πi] 4×1 are distributed in proportion to the NBS, i.e. to compute a [P] 4×5 matrix, which satisfies Eq (12):

We use the computation algorithm presented in the previous section, i.e. the random partition of the pie-set into two subsets and the continuous random partitions of the agent-coalitions for n-1 times, as illustrated in Figure 2.

  1. 1. Step 1: Randomly partition of the pie-set J into two subsets: {1}, and {2, 3, 4, 5}.
  2. 2. Step 2: Randomly partition of the grand-coalition N into two coalitions: {1}, and {2, 3, 4}.
  3. 3. Step 3: A MCS model is developed, in which the Ci, Π j are inputs and the Π{1}, Π{2,3,4} are the outputs, according to the following Eqs (25), (26):

(25) (26)

  1. 4. Step 4: Initially, we select a specific value: . For this value, the: , while from Eqs (22), (23), we compute: and the :
    (27) (28)
    For the scenario , we run the MCS and we get: σ{1} = 6232764, σ{2,3,4} = 873019. It is clear that this scenario does not satisfy Eq (24), because:
    Further, we examine alternative scenarios arising from different values of , and we compute the unique ratios that satisfy Eq (24):
  2. 5. Step 5: We return to Step 2 and use the ratios: in the random partition of the {2, 3, 4} coalition into two coalitions: {2,3} and {4}. According to this partition, we compute the unique ratios: . Further, we return to Step 2 and we use the ratios in the partition of the coalition {2, 3} into {2} and {3}, in order to calculate the unique ratios:
  3. 6. Step 6: We estimate for each agent the ratios in each subsets of pies: {1}, and {2, 3, 4, 5}, through the product of the ratios of the agent-coalitions in which the agent is included:
    • and

Moreover, due to the fact that each agent’s ratios are equal in all pies of each subset, we estimate:

and we illustrate the [P] 4×5 matrix:

(29)(7) Step 7: In order to verify the results, we develop another MCS model, where the estimated [P] 4×5, the [Π j] 5×1, and the [C i] 4×1 matrices are inputs, while the [Π i] 4×1 is the output according to Eq (9):

(9)We run the simulation that gives the following results:

and . These results verify that the overall surplus is divided with fairness, as the dividends allocated to all agents are distributed in proportion to the NBS:(30)

Other solutions for asymmetric NBS with unequal divisions.

As can be seen in Table 2, in the specific case (where five pies: m = 5 are allocated to four agents: n = 4), there are 225 different [P] 4×5 matrices that ensure fairness within the NBS. For instance, if we follow a different partition set, as illustrated in Figure 3, i.e. the same partitions of the agent-coalitions into a pair for n-1 = 3 times, and a different partition of the pie-set J = {1,2,3,4,5} into two other subsets: {2,3} and {1,4,5}, then we calculate another [P] 4×5 matrix:(31)

However, if we use this matrix along with the [Π j] 5×1,[C i] 4×1 as inputs and the [Πi] 4×1 as output in another MCS model, then the simulation gives: and , verifying that Eq (12) is also fulfilled with this [P] 4×5 matrix.

Eq (12) can be also satisfied with the set of partitions presented in Figure 4. Specifically, through the partition of J = {1,2,3,4,5} into {1}, {2,3,4,5} subsets and the partition of N = {1,2,3,4} into {3,4}, {1,2}, and the further partitions into {4}, {3} and {1}, {2}, respectively, we get the following[P] 4×5 matrix:(32)with which the MCS gives:

, and .

Conclusively, it can be seen from Eqs (29), (31) and (32) that these [P] 4×5 matrices are different, however provide equal results since the dividends allocated to all agents are distributed in proportion to the bargaining outcome U that is the asymmetric NBS with unequal divisions.

Asymmetric NBS with equal divisions.

In the second case, the bargaining outcome is the asymmetric NBS where the surplus is divided equally according to Eq (6): U1 = U2 = U3 = U4 = 0.25. If we follow the same set of partitions presented in Figure 2, i.e. partition of J into two subsets: {1}, {2, 3, 4, 5} and partition of N into {1}, {2, 3, 4}, and the further partition into {4}, {2, 3}, and the further partition into {2}, {3}, then we compute the following [P] 4×5 matrix:(33)

Moreover, if we develop another MCS model, where the estimated [P] 4×5, the [Π j] 5×1 and the [C i] 4×1 matrices are inputs and the [Π i] 4×1 is the output in Eq (9), then the simulation gives: , and . Clearly, this matrix ensures fairness within the asymmetric NBS with equal divisions, as it fulfils Eq (12):

Applications

In the previous numerical example, a generalized case of a cooperative venture was considered, in which agents with different disagreement payoffs agreed in a specific allocation of the overall surplus. However, there are various real life situations, to which the computation algorithm presented here can be applied. Specifically, it can be applied to all situations that can be formulated within Eq (9):(9)

Indicatively, we present the following cases:

  1. • Let’s consider a water allocation problem, in which n authorities (agents) with fixed disagreement payoffs of water (C1,…,Cn), negotiate over the division of the water collected from different sources (pies), e.g. from rivers, rainwater tanks, wastewater treatment plants, etc. If these pies follow normal probability distributions and all agents are risk-neutrals and agree in a specific NBS (either symmetric or asymmetric), then the method presented here can be effectively applied. In particular, agents can compute a [P] n×m matrix, which represents the ratio of the water from each source that should be distributed in each area, in order to ensure fairness within the NBS.
  2. • Another example is a solid waste management problem, where the managers (agents) of n waste incineration plants, who have fixed disagreement payoffs of waste (C1,…,Cn), negotiate over the division of the volume of solid waste (pies) arising from different areas. Specifically, if these pies follow normal probability distributions and the risk-neutral agents (who want to maximize the volume of waste treated in their plants, in order to maximize their profits) agree in a specific NBS, then the proposed algorithm can be applied for computation to the volume of waste that should be distributed in each plant from each area.
  3. • Additionally, the computation algorithm can be applied to supply chain networks where n risk-neutral agents (manufacturers or/and suppliers or/and retailers), having fixed disagreement monetary payoffs (C1,…,Cn), negotiate over the division of the revenues and costs that are yielded through cooperation. In this case, the pies represent the operation revenues, e.g. from different products’ selling, and the respective costs, e.g. infrastructure, advertising, distribution and storage costs, etc. Specifically, since the demand is not realized when the network is formed, these pies can be assumed as stochastic variables that follow normal probability distributions. If agents negotiate and agree in a specific NBS (either symmetric or asymmetric) for the division of the overall profits (surplus) of the network, then the proposed algorithm can be applied for computation to the ratio of each pie that should be allocated to each agent.

Methods

We compute the possible [P] n×m matrices that are presented in Table 2 by using the Wolfram Research Mathematica Version 7.0 software. For the development of MCS models within the computation algorithm, we suggest using specialized software, in order to get accurate results.

Conclusions

Over the last decades, one of the most widely examined problems is the fair division of a surplus among agents. Herein, we focus on cases where multiple stochastic pies should be shared among agents with fixed disagreement payoffs, according to a specific NBS for the division of the overall surplus. Particularly, we consider that fairness is achieved when the stochastic dividends which are allocated to agents are distributed in proportion to the NBS. We introduce a novel method that can be applied to various situations, in order to compute the ratio of each pie that should be allocated to each agent. It is proved that there are finite possible solutions depending on the partitions of the pie-set into two subsets and the continuous partitions of the grand-coalition into two coalitions, until eventually all agents form singletons. We have assumed in this paper that all agents are risk-neutrals and the stochastic pies are divisible and follow normal probability distribution functions. Without making these assumptions, the development of respective algorithms in cases where agents with different risk preferences (risk-averse/neutral/seeking) are not indifferent between the m pies, or the stochastic pies are indivisible or follow asymmetric probability distributions, e.g. lognormal, can be subjects for future research. Future papers can also focus on the application of other solution concepts, such as the Shapley value, the core, and the Nucleolus to stochastic environments, where the size of the pie over which agents are negotiating may vary stochastically. Conclusively, the computation algorithm introduced with this paper can be a useful tool for decision-making under uncertainty, as it helps agents to estimate solutions that ensure fairness within a symmetric or asymmetric NBS.

Supporting Information

Text S1.

Proofs of Theorems and Propositions.

https://doi.org/10.1371/journal.pone.0044535.s001

(DOC)

Acknowledgments

The authors deeply appreciate the Editors and two anonymous reviewers for their insightful comments and suggestions.

Author Contributions

Conceived and designed the experiments: ACK KA. Performed the experiments: ACK IPT. Analyzed the data: ACK KA IPT. Contributed reagents/materials/analysis tools: ACK AS. Wrote the paper: ACK.

References

  1. 1. Aristotle “Nicomachean Ethics, 1130b–1132b” (1984). In: Barnes J, editor. The complete works of Aristotle. Princeton: Princeton University Press.
  2. 2. Binmore K (2001) How and why did fairness norms evolve? In: Runciman WG, editor. Proceedings of the British Academy Oxford University Press. New York. 149–170.
  3. 3. Renna P, Argoneto P (2011) Capacity sharing in a network of independent factories: A cooperative game theory approach. Robot Comput Integr Manuf 27: 405–417.
  4. 4. Guardiola LA, Meca A, Timmer J (2007) Cooperation and profit allocation in distribution chains. Decis Support Syst 44: 17–27.
  5. 5. Tijs SH, Driessen TSH (1986) Game theory and cost allocation problems. Manage Sci 32: 1015–1028.
  6. 6. Moulin H (1987) Equal or Proportional Division of a Surplus and Other Methods. Int J Game Theory 16: 161–186.
  7. 7. von Neumann J, Morgenstern O (1944) Theory of Games and Economic Behavior. Princeton NJ: Princeton University Press.
  8. 8. Shapley LS (1953) A Value for n-person Games. In: Kuhn HW, Tucker AW, editors. Contributions to the Theory of Games II, Annals of Mathematical Studies vol 28, Princeton University Press. 307–317.
  9. 9. Gillies D (1959) Solutions to General Nonzero Sum Games. Ann Math Stu 40: 47–85.
  10. 10. Schmeidler D (1969) The Nucleolus of a Characteristic Function Game. SIAM J Appl Math 17: 1163–1170.
  11. 11. Kalai E, Samet D (1985) Monotonic solutions to general cooperative games. Econometrica 53: 307–327.
  12. 12. Young HP (1985) Monotonic Solutions of Cooperative Games. Int J Game Theory 14: 65–72.
  13. 13. Chun Y (1988) The proportional solution for rights problems. Math Soc Sci 15: 231–246.
  14. 14. Nash J 1950 The bargaining problem. Econometrica 18, 155–162.
  15. 15. Wong KKL (2010) A Geometrical Perspective for the Bargaining Problem. PLoS ONE 5(4): e10331 doi:10.1371/journal.pone.0010331.
  16. 16. Madani K (2011) Hydropower Licensing and Climate Change: Insights from Cooperative Game Theory. Adv Water Res 34: 174–183.
  17. 17. Harsanyi JC (1959) A bargaining model for the cooperative n-person game. In: Tucker AW, Luce DR, editors. Contributions to the Theory of Games. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press. 324–356.
  18. 18. Harsanyi JC (1963) A simplified bargaining model for the n-person game. Int Econ Rev 4: 194–220.
  19. 19. Kalai E (1977) Nonsymmetric Nash solutions and replications of 2-person bargaining. Int J Game Theory 6: 129–133.
  20. 20. Roth AE (1979) Axiomatic Models of Bargaining. Lecture Notes in Economics and Mathematical Systems: 170, Springer Verlag. 19–20.
  21. 21. Barbanel JB, Brams SJ (2004) Cake division with minimal cuts: envy-free procedures for three persons, four persons, and beyond. Math Soc Sci 48: 251–269.
  22. 22. Bughin J (1999) Oligopoly profit-sharing contracts and the firm’s systematic risk. Eur Econ Rev 43: 549–558.
  23. 23. Linh CT, Hong Y (2009) Channel coordination through a revenue sharing contract in a two-period newsboy problem. Eur J Oper Res 198: 822–829.
  24. 24. Hoefer M (2012) Strategic cooperation in cost sharing games. Int J Game Theory (In press), DOI 10.1007/s00182-011-0312-8.
  25. 25. Kunter M (2012) Coordination via cost and revenue sharing in manufacturer-retailer channels. Eur J Oper Res 216: 477–486.
  26. 26. Karmperis AC, Aravossis K, Sotirchos A, Tatsiopoulos I (2012) Coordination of multi-agents with a revenue-cost-sharing mechanism: A cooperative game theory approach. Int J Math Mod Meth Appl Sci 6: 209–221.
  27. 27. Hennet J-C, Mahjoub S (2010) Toward the fair sharing of profit in a supply network formation. Int J Prod Econ 127: 112–120.
  28. 28. Li S, Zhu Z, Huang L (2009) Supply chain coordination and decision making under consignment contract with revenue sharing. Int J Prod Econ 120: 88–99.
  29. 29. Ding H, Guo B, Liu Z (2011) Information sharing and profit allotment based on supply chain cooperation. Int J Prod Econ 133: 70–79.
  30. 30. van den Brink R, van der Laan G, Moes N (2011) Fair agreements for sharing international rivers with multiple springs and externalities. J Environ Econ Manage 63: 388–403.
  31. 31. Saleh Y, Gürler Ü, Berk E (2011) Centralized and decentralized management of groundwater with multiple users. Eur J Oper Res 215: 244–256.
  32. 32. Lo Nigro G, Abbate L (2011) Risk assessment and profit sharing in business networks. Int J Prod Econ 131: 234–241.
  33. 33. Shi CV, Zhao X, Xia Y (2010) The setting of profit targets for target oriented divisions. Eur J Oper Res 206: 86–92.
  34. 34. Karmperis AC, Sotirchos A, Aravossis K, Tatsiopoulos I (2012) Risk based process for funding scheme evaluation of Public Private Partnerships. In: Recent Researches in Applied Mathematics and Economics, Proceedings of the 6th International Conference on Applied Mathematics, Simulation, Modeling (ASM’ Kambe T, Bulucea CA, Arapatsakos C, editors. 12): 20–25.
  35. 35. Carraro C, Marchiori C, Sgobbi A (2005) Advances in negotiation theory: Bargaining, coalitions and fairness. World Bank Policy Research, Working Paper 3642, 20–21.
  36. 36. Mitropoulou ChCh, Lagaros ND, Papadrakakis M (2011) Life-cycle cost assessment of optimally designed reinforced concrete buildings under seismic actions. Reliab Eng Syst Safe 96: 1311–1331.
  37. 37. Kepaptsoglou K, Karlaftis MG, Li Z (2010) Optimizing Pricing Policies in Park-and-Ride Facilities: A Model and Decision Support System with Application. J Transport Syst Eng Inform Techn 10: 53–65.
  38. 38. Karmperis AC, Sotirchos A, Aravossis K, Tatsiopoulos I (2012) Waste management project’s alternatives: A risk-based multi-criteria assessment (RBMCA) approach. Waste Manage 32: 194–212.
  39. 39. Tziralis G, Kirytopoulos K, Rentizelas A, Tatsiopoulos I (2009) Holistic Investment Assessment: Optimization, Risk Appraisal and Decision Making. Manage Dec Econ 30: 393–403.
  40. 40. Wu DD, Olson D (2010) Enterprise risk management: a DEA VaR approach in vendor selection. Int J Prod Res 48: 4919–4932.
  41. 41. Csóka P, Pintér M (2011) On the Impossibility of Fair Risk Allocation. Accessed: http://econpapers.repec.org/paper/hasdiscpr/1117.htm 2011.
  42. 42. Binmore K, Shaked A, Sutton J (1989) An outside option experiment. Q J Econ 104: 753–770.
  43. 43. Helbing D, Johansson A (2010) Cooperation, Norms, and Revolutions: A Unified Game-Theoretical Approach. PLoS ONE 5(10): e12530 doi:10.1371/journal.pone.0012530.
  44. 44. Supatgiat C, Zhang RO, Birge JR (2001) Equilibrium values in a competitive power exchange market. Comp Econ 17: 93–121.
  45. 45. Rausser GC (2000) Collective choice in water resources system. In: Dinar A, editor. The Political Economy of Water Pricing Reforms. Oxford University Press. 52–53.
  46. 46. Csóka P, Herings PJ-J, Kóczy LA (2009) Stable allocations of risk. Games Econ Behav 67: 266–276.
  47. 47. Baek SK, Choi J-K, Kim BJ (2012) Dworkin’s Paradox. PLoS ONE 7(6): e38529 doi:10.1371/journal.pone.0038529.