Skip to main content
Advertisement
  • Loading metrics

Moral Imagination: The Missing Component in Global Health

  • Solomon R. Benatar

The deplorable state of global health and the failure to improve this state have been debated extensively. Recent editorials in the Lancet in relation to the failure of Roll Back Malaria and the potential failure of the 3 by 5 programme [1,2] illustrate how disappointment, surprise, and admonitions about such failures are usually followed by optimism about the success envisaged from future efforts [1,3].

There are several possible reasons for our failure to make adequate progress in improving global health. First, it seems that there is generally more interest in doing research to acquire new knowledge than in using existing knowledge, unless it is commercially profitable—illustrating how market forces are a more powerful influence on the practice of medicine than health needs [4]. Second, concern for those who are most severely affected by ill health seems to be generally transient, perhaps because they are anonymous and out of sight, but maybe also because their lives are less highly valued [5,6]. Third, there is a tendency to focus on new technologies through “silo” (narrowly contained) approaches to improving global health [7–9]. Fourth, there is insufficient attention to the social determinants of health [10,11].

Finally, while many are concerned about the plight of others, collective action through nongovernmental organisations can only achieve limited results, and there is reluctance to acknowledge and more explicitly address the indirect, causal, complex global system forces that underlie poverty and many fatal diseases [5,11–15]. Fortunately, there is now growing recognition that new infectious diseases pose a major threat to human health and security worldwide [16,17], and that imaginative new solutions are needed to improve global health [18,19].

While it is entirely appropriate to consider scientific and technological advances and economic growth as necessary for social progress, it is arguable that these will not be sufficient to ensure movement towards a more just world in which the health of whole populations could be improved. The controversy about globalisation versus antiglobalisation will not be revisited here, except to say that the debate should rather be about how globalisation can be modified to extend the benefits of progress more widely [20,21].

In this essay, I begin by suggesting that achieving substantial improvements in global health will depend on acknowledging that poor health at the level of whole populations reflects systemic dysfunction in a complex world. I then address why development aid is a necessary but not a sufficient solution for improving global health. I conclude with the idea that greater moral imagination (the ability of individuals and communities to empathise with others) and innovative 21st century approaches are required to break the impasse we currently face in improving global health.

An Unstable and Dysfunctional World

In the domain of economics, there is a disjunction between massive economic growth over the past 50 years and fair distribution of new wealth [22]. The global economy has increased 7-fold since 1950, yet the disparity in per capita gross domestic product between the 20 richest and the 20 poorest nations has more than doubled between 1960 and 1995 [23]. As a result, there are ever-widening disparities between rich and poor (Figures 1 and 2), and almost half the world's population lives on less than US$2 per day [24]. Disproportionate pursuit of short-term self-interest, fostered by market fundamentalism, emphasises production of goods for consumption by individuals, corporations, and governments, while long-term interests and the production of public goods for whole populations are undervalued [25].

thumbnail
Relationship between life expectancy and income per capita

(Figure adapted from [69])

https://doi.org/10.1371/journal.pmed.0020400.g002

Economic stability is threatened when aggregate economic growth is valued as an end in itself rather than as a means to improving human lives, and consequently, there is a failure to achieve a more just distribution of economic and social benefits [26]. Economic dysfunction persists when conventional economic theory continues to be revered and applied despite its many failures [26–29], and thus reduces the potential for improving global health and increasing human security worldwide [30].

In the domain of political and social life, instability is revealed by ongoing wars, ethnic conflict, fundamentalist attitudes, failed responses to genocide in many countries, large-scale disruption of communities, refugeeism, terrorism, fragmentation of health services, and attrition of public health-care services—all reflecting a lack of global leadership and a failure to achieve basic human rights for more people in the world [5,13,14,26,30,31]. Moreover, the full potential of the human rights approach is greatly diminished by a predominant focus on civil and political rights. Insufficient attention is paid to the social, cultural, and economic rights that are essential for human flourishing, and which are part of the “indivisible human rights” package described in the Universal Declaration of Human Rights, which most human rights activists use as their source of authority. It seems that higher value is placed on the rights and lives of those with resources than on the common good and the lives of the poor, and inadequate attention is given to identifying and motivating those who have duties to uphold a broad spectrum of rights [32,33].

These shortcomings, together with ecological instability from environmental degradation, global warming, and ongoing loss of biodiversity, arguably facilitate the creation of niches for the emergence and propagation of new infectious diseases, promote the development of multidrug resistance [34], and make it more difficult to maintain the social structures required to provide care and support for so many in need [35].

Development Aid: A Necessary but Insufficient Solution

Greenwood's call for increased development aid to provide the US$2–US$5 needed for each year of life that could be saved through an effective worldwide malaria control programme [3] resembles the approaches taken for tuberculosis and HIV/AIDS (http://www.theglobalfund.org). It must be gratefully acknowledged that generous philanthropy from concerned individuals and many foundations, organisations, and new global initiatives can, and do, make valued contributions to improving the health and health care of marginalised people in the world. Development aid from many countries should also be welcomed, and recent endeavours to increase aid from the current average of 0.23% gross domestic product to the recommended 0.7% are admirable [36].

However, development aid has been progressively reduced in recent years, and is increasingly being directed towards emergency humanitarian aid and the perceived security needs of wealthy nations, rather than towards sustainable development [37,38]. Therefore, the main problem is not merely lack of philanthropy and development aid. More poignantly, the problem is how the high profile given to relatively small amounts of aid eclipses recognition of the fact that financial, human, and other material resources are continuously being extracted from developing countries by wealthy nations striving for their own ongoing economic growth [19,24].

Modern trade rules [39], bribery and other means of controlling national economies and the lives of millions of poor people [40], and recruitment of health professionals trained at the expense of developing countries to sustain health care in wealthy countries [41] all reflect new forms of exploitation that result in much more being extracted from developing countries than is given to them in aid or in any other form. For example, annual farming subsidies of US$350 billion in industrialised countries [42] and trade protectionism cost developing countries US$50 billion annually in export earnings [43]. Allowing farmers in developing countries to sell their products at a fair price and not in competition with massive subsidies could eliminate the need for development aid [39,44].

Debt is another major problem. Poor countries' debt (US$2.2 trillion in 1997) has been associated with, and perpetuated through, arms trading (often coercively linked to aid) [45–47]. Such debt, particularly sub-Saharan Africa's debt of US$275 billion, fostered by both eager lenders and often corrupt borrowers can never be repaid. Sustaining debt perpetuates economic dependence and human misery. Resulting annual interest payments, of greater magnitude than the US$21 billion annual aid donated to Africa, cripple health and other social services and stultify development [48,49].

While some countries have achieved economic development, this has been generally less than desired and, sadly, lacking in most of sub-Saharan Africa. Moreover, much done in the name of development has been counterproductive, with adverse effects on the potential for globally improved human security [50–53]. The meaning of development and its evaluation needs to be reconsidered. Development means more than overall economic growth, and must include social progress, for example, in basic living conditions, education, and access to health care, so that all can have the opportunity to reach their achievable human capacities [50,54,55].

The unpalatable facts about how development is stultified are not being adequately confronted, and little attempt is made to acknowledge and address the complex systemic forces that sustain poverty and poor health [19,24]. Instead, obfuscation by politicians and indomitable optimism focused on economics, science, and human rights all promote continued hope for improving health in the developing world through market forces and new technologies [7–9].

Inadequate Moral Imagination

Some critical questions about world poverty have been asked and need to be answered [24]. Why does extreme poverty of almost half of humankind (income of less that US$2 per day) continue despite scientific, technological, economic, and moral progress? How do we explain why affluent individuals and wealthy nations are not morally embarrassed that so many people can be relegated to lives of poor quality with such limited opportunities to reach their full human potential? What does support (by individuals and nations) for processes that aggravate and sustain poverty tell us about ourselves and about the values we hold deeply? How can the rich remain secure in a world in which so many are so desperately poor that they may be provoked to rise up and rebel? Widening disparities within wealthy nations add another troubling dimension [56].

Many privileged people believe that poverty is not the fault of wealthy countries, but rather the result of bad government elsewhere. This is, indeed, partially true, and the prominent exposure of the extent of corruption and poor governance, for example in Africa [24,36,44,57], should be followed by sustained condemnation, retribution, and prevention. However, much less openly discussed is the complicity of powerful nations in supporting leaders who are despots and kleptocrats—by legitimising their right to sell their countries' natural resources, spend profligately on themselves, and incur debts that their impoverished citizens must repay [24,52]. Because wealthy nations, and by association their citizens, are deeply implicated in the generation and maintenance of forces that perpetuate social injustice and poverty, they need to face their responsibilities to alleviate the lives of those most adversely affected [24,52]. Reliance solely on perpetual philanthropy is clearly not the long-term solution to global health problems.

While we talk increasingly about disparities in wealth and health in an unjust world, most privileged people remain complacent about the suffering of the poor—both distant and within our midst [58,59]. In considering the many genocides across the world during the 20th century, Jonathan Glover has suggested that it is only moral imagination (our ability to imagine ourselves in the shoes of others) that can enable us to alter our outlook and actions significantly [60]. Our moral imagination is dulled, and insight into our global interdependence is diminished by insufficient public acknowledgment of how the quest of wealthy nations for endless economic growth, and luxuries that their citizens expect, has profoundly adverse effects on access to basic necessities of life for millions of others [24,26,49]. The ability to empathise with others requires the critical examination of our individual lives and of our nations' actions, the capacity to see ourselves as bound to all other human beings, and the sensitivity to imagine what it might be like to be a person living a very deprived and threatened life [24,61,62].

Making a diagnosis of social ills, like making diagnoses in medical practice, is much easier than providing effective remedies [63]. The magnitude and importance of achieving solidarity and cooperation in an interdependent world calls for a major research programme and considerable scholarship from many disciplines. Some pointers have been provided [18–21,24,64–66].

If lack of moral imagination were to be seen as one of the grand challenges for global health, resources and scholarly energy would surely be applied to promoting such imagination and to seeking innovative new approaches to improving global health. The quest for improved global health will be elusive if we continue to neglect the upstream forces that cause, sustain, and aggravate the poverty and misery that characterise the lives of almost half the world's population. The writing is on the wall [67].

Acknowledgments

I am grateful to Renee Fox (and to Amir Attaran, who reviewed the manuscript for PLoS Medicine) for their constructive comments. This work was supported in part by a grant from the United States National Institutes of Health's Fogarty International Center to the University of Cape Town's capacity building programme in International Research Ethics in Southern Africa (IRENSA Programme Director S. R. Benatar), and by the University of Toronto.

References

  1. 1. (2005) Reversing the failures of Roll Back Malaria. Lancet 365: 1439.
  2. 2. (2005) Predicting the failure of 3 by 5. Lancet 365: 1597.
  3. 3. Greenwood BM, Bojang K, Whitty CJM, Target GAT (2005) Malaria. Lancet 365: 1487–1498.
  4. 4. Trouiller P, Olliaro P, Torreele E, Orbinski J, Laing R, et al. (2002) Drug development for neglected diseases: A deficient market and a public health failure. Lancet 359: 2188–2194.
  5. 5. Benatar SR (1998) Global disparities in health and human rights. Am J Public Health 88: 295–300.
  6. 6. Gandy M, Zumla A (2003) The return of the white plague: Global poverty and the ‘new’ tuberculosis. London: Verso. 320 p.
  7. 7. Singer PA, Daar AS (2001) Harnessing genomics and biotechnology to improve global health equity. Science 294: 87–89.
  8. 8. Acharya T, Daar AS, Thorsteinsdóttir H, Dowdeswell E, Singer PA (2004) Strengthening the role of genomics in global health. PLoS Med 1: e40.
  9. 9. World Health Organization (2002) Genomics and world health: Report of the Advisory Committee on Health Research. Geneva: World Health Organization. Available: http://www.who.int/gb/ebwha/pdf_files/EB112/eeb1124.pdf. Accessed 26 October 2005.
  10. 10. Marmot M (2005) Social determinants of health inequalities. Lancet 365: 1099.
  11. 11. Birn AE (2005) Gates' grandest challenge: Transcending technology as public health ideology. Lancet 366: 514–519. Available: http://image.thelancet.com/extras/04art6429web.pdf. Accessed 26 October 2005.
  12. 12. Benatar SR (2005) The HIV/AIDS pandemic: A sign of instability in a complex global system. In: Van Niekerk AA, Kopelman L, editors. Ethics and AIDS in Africa: The challenge to our thinking. Cape Town: David Philip Press. pp. 71–83.
  13. 13. Beaglehole R, editor. (2003) Global public health: A new era. Oxford: Oxford University Press. 284 p.
  14. 14. Farmer P (2003) Pathologies of power. Berkeley: University of California Press. 402 p.
  15. 15. Green M, Hulme D (2005) From correlates and characteristics to causes: Thinking about poverty from a chronic poverty perspective. World Dev 33: 867–879.
  16. 16. Garrett L (2005) The next pandemic? Foreign Aff 84: 3–23.
  17. 17. Garrett L (2005) The lessons of HIV/AIDS. Foreign Aff 84: 51–65.
  18. 18. Benatar SR, Daar AS, Singer PA (2003) Global health ethics: The rationale for mutual caring. Int Aff 79: 107–138.
  19. 19. McKee M, Gilmore AB, Schwalbe N (2005) International cooperation and health. Part 1. J Epidemiol Community Health 59: 628–631.
  20. 20. Sandbrook R, editor. (2003) Civilizing globalization: A survival guide. Albany: State University of New York Press. 320 p.
  21. 21. Royal Danish Ministry for Foreign Affairs (2000) Building a global community: Globalisation and the common good. Copenhagen: Royal Danish Ministry for Foreign Affairs. 272 p.
  22. 22. Coburn D (2003) Globalization, neoliberalism and health. In: Sandbrook R, editor. Civilizing globalization. Albany: State University of New York Press. pp. 27–38.
  23. 23. World Watch Institute (2003) Rich–poor gap widening. Washington (D.C): Vital Signs. pp. 88–89. Available: http://www.worldwatch.org/features/vsow/2003/11/12/. Accessed 26 October 2005.
  24. 24. Pogge T (2002) World poverty and human rights. Cambridge: Polity Press. 265 p.
  25. 25. Kaul I, Grunberg I, Stern MA, editors. (1999) Global public goods: International cooperation in the 21st century. New York: Oxford University Press. 546 p.
  26. 26. Amin S (1997) Capitalism in the age of globalisation. London: Zed Books. 158 p.
  27. 27. Galbraith JK (1960) The affluent society. Boston: Houghton Mifflin. 336 p.
  28. 28. Galbraith JK (2004) The economics of innocent fraud: Truth for our time. Boston: Houghton Mifflin. 64 p.
  29. 29. Heilbroner R, Milberg W (1995) The crisis of vision in modern economic thought. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. 125 p.
  30. 30. Hong E (2000) Globalisation and the impact on health: A third world view. Savar (Bangladesh): The Peoples' Health Assembly. Available: http://www.phmovement.org/pubs/issuepapers/hong.html. Accessed 26 October 2005.
  31. 31. Rotblat J, editor. Pugwash Conferences on Science and World Affairs (1997) World citizenship: Allegiance to humanity. London: Macmillan. 234 p.
  32. 32. Falk R (2000) Human rights horizons: The pursuit of justice in a globalizing world. New York: Routledge. 288 p.
  33. 33. Felice WF (1996) Taking suffering seriously: The importance of collective human rights. Albany: State University of New York Press. 253 p.
  34. 34. Garret L (1994) The coming plague: Newly emerging diseases in a world out of balance. New York: Farrar, Strauss and Giroux. 768 p.
  35. 35. Bakker I, Gill S, editors. (2003) Power, production and social reproduction. Human in/security in the global political economy. New York: Palgrave Macmillan. 256 p.
  36. 36. Birdsall N (2005) How to help poor countries. Foreign Aff 84: 136–152.
  37. 37. Lancaster C (2000) Transforming foreign aid: United States assistance in the 21st century. Washington (D.C.): Institute for International Economics. 108 p.
  38. 38. Woods N (2005) The shifting politics of foreign aid. Int Aff 81: 393–409.
  39. 39. Koivusalo M (2003) The impact of WTO agreements on health and development policies. In: Deacon B, Ollila E, Koivusalo M, Stubbs P, editors. Global social governances: Themes and prospects. Helsinki: Ministry for Foreign Affairs. pp. 77–129.
  40. 40. Werlin H (2005) Corruption and foreign aid in Africa. Orbis 49: 517–527.
  41. 41. Dovlo D (2005) Taking more than a fair share? The migration of health professionals from poor to rich countries. PLoS Med 2: e109.
  42. 42. Elliott L (2003 May 22) Don't let the rich cry poor over aid. Guardian Weekly 12:
  43. 43. Kristof ND (2003 May 27) What did you do during the African holocaust? New York Times 25. Sect A.
  44. 44. Guest R (2004) The shackled continent: Power, corruption and foreign aid. Washington (D.C.): Smithsonian Books. 288 p.
  45. 45. Sivard RL (1996) World military and social expenditures 1996, 16th edition. Washington (D.C.): World Priorities Press. 56 p.
  46. 46. Sidel VW (1995) The international arms trade and its impact on health. BMJ 311: 1677–1680.
  47. 47. Pettifor A (1996) Debt, the most potent form of slavery: A discussion of the role of western lending policies in supporting the economies of poor countries. London: Debt Crisis Network. 37 p.
  48. 48. Anonymous (2003 May 25) Into Africa: Special report. Toronto Star 1–5. Sect F.
  49. 49. Logie DE, Benatar SR (1997) Africa in the 21st century: Can despair be turned to hope? BMJ 315: 1144–1146.
  50. 50. Labonte R, Schrecker T, Sanders D, Meeus W (2004) Fatal indifference: The G8 and global health. Cape Town: University of Cape Town Press. 378 p.
  51. 51. Hancock G (1989) Lords of poverty. London: MacMillan. 234 p.
  52. 52. Rist G (1997) The history of development: From western origins to global faith. London: Zed Books. 320 p.
  53. 53. Purdy M (2005) Countering terrorism: The missing pillar. Int J 60: 3–24.
  54. 54. Sen A (1999) Development as freedom. New York: Anchor Books. 384 p.
  55. 55. Bensimon C, Benatar SR (2005) Developing sustainability: A new metaphor for progress. Theor Med Bioeth. In press.
  56. 56. Raphael D (2000) Health inequalities in Canada: Current discourses and implications for public health action. Crit Public Health 10: 193–216.
  57. 57. Anonymous (2005 March 11) Erasing the scar. The Economist. Available: http://www.economist.com/agenda/displayStory.cfm?story_id=3758983. Accessed 26 October 2005.
  58. 58. Galbraith JK (1992) The culture of contentment. Boston: Houghton Mifflin. 195 p.
  59. 59. Power S (2002) A problem from hell: America and the age of genocide. New York: Basic Books. 656 p.
  60. 60. Glover J (2001) Humanity: A moral history of the twentieth century. New Haven: Yale University Press. 480 p.
  61. 61. Nussbaum MC (1997) Cultivating humanity: A classical defense of reform in liberal education. Cambridge (Massachusetts): Harvard University Press. 328 p.
  62. 62. Benatar SR (2004) Towards progress in resolving dilemmas in international research ethics. J Law Med Ethics 32: 574–582.
  63. 63. Benatar SR (2001) The coming catastrophe in international health: An analogy with lung cancer. Int J 56: 611–631.
  64. 64. Benatar SR (1997) Streams of global change. In: Bankowski Z, Bryant JH, Gallagher J, editors. Ethics, Equity and Health for All. Geneva: Council for International Organizations of Medical Sciences. pp. 75–85.
  65. 65. Benatar SR (2003) Ethics and tropical diseases: A global perspective. In: Cook G, Zumla A, editors. Manson's tropical diseases, 21st edition. Edinburgh: Elsevier Science. pp. 85–93.
  66. 66. Benatar SR, Fox RC (2005) Meeting threats to global health: A call for American leadership. Perspect Biol Med 48: 344–361.
  67. 67. Blair T (2005) Our common interest: Report of the Commission for Africa. London: Commission for Africa. Available: http://www.commissionforafrica.org/english/report/thereport/english/11-03-05_cr_report.pdf. Accessed 26 October 2005.
  68. 68. Anonymous (1999) The champagne glass of world poverty. BMJ 318. Available: http://bmj.bmjjournals.com/cgi/content/full/318/7189/0. Accessed 31 October 2005.
  69. 69. The World Bank (1993) The world development report 1993: Investing in health. New York: Oxford University Press. 352 p.